PROFESSORIAL
SPEECH,
THE
FIRST
AMENDMENT,
AND
LEGISLATIVE
RESTRICTIONS
ON
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
Keith
E.
Whittington*
Academic
freedom
enjoys
an
uncertain
status
in
American
constitutional
law
under
the
First
Amendment.
It
is
particularly
unclear
how
the
First
Amendment
applies
when
it
comes
to
professorial
speech
in
the
classroom.
This
lack
of
clarity
has
grave
implications
in
the
current
political
environment.
There
is
now
an
unprecedented
wave
of
legislative
proposals
aimed
at
curtailing
teaching
and
discussing
controversial
topics
relating
to
race
and
gender
in
state-university
classrooms,
and
the
constitutionality
of
such
measures
will
soon
need
to
be
resolved.
This
Article
sets
out
a
new
argument
for
protecting
from
legislative
interference
the
way
faculty
at
state
universities
teach
their
courses.
Building
on
existing
First
Amendment
jurisprudence
regarding
academic
freedom
and
government-
employee
speech,
the
Article
lays
out
the
constitutional
infirmities
with
anti-Critical
Race
Theory
proposals
and
clarifies
the
scope
of
an
individual
constitutional
liberty
in
the
context
of
professorial
speech.
TABLE
OF
CONTENTS
IN
TR
O
D
U
CTIO
N
...............................................................................
464
I.
THE
CULTURE
WAR
AND
ANTI-CRITICAL
RACE
THEORY
LEGISLATION
.......................................................
467
II.
THE
COLD
WAR
AND
ANTI-SUBVERSIVE
LEGISLATION
........................................................................
477
III.
THE
FIRST
AMENDMENT
AND
ACADEMIC
FREEDOM
...............................................................................
482
IV.
PICKERING,
GARCETTI,
AND
ACADEMIC
F
R
E
E
D
O
M
...............................................................................
492
V.
GOVERNMENT
SPEECH
AND
PRIVATE
SPEECH
IN
STATE
UNIVERSITIES....................................513
*
William
Nelson
Cromwell
Professor
of
Politics,
Princeton
University;
visiting
fellow,
Hoover
Institution.
My
thanks
for
the
helpful
comments
from
Donald
Downs,
Matthew
Finkin,
Howard
Gillman,
Frank
Michelman,
Robert
Post,
David
Rabban,
and
Timothy
Zick.
463
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
CONCLUSION
...................................................................................
522
INTRODUCTION
We
are
in
the
midst
of
an unprecedented
legislative
assault
on
traditional
commitments
to
academic
freedom
in
state
universities.
Despite
the
robust
protections
for
controversial
speech
that
the
Supreme
Court
has
built
up
under the
First
Amendment
over
the
past
century,
the
constitutional
status
of
professorial
classroom
speech
remains
unclear.
This
Article
brings
clarity
to
that
problem.
It
demonstrates
that
the
so-called
anti-Critical
Race
Theory
("anti-
CRT")
bills
impermissibly
burden
constitutionally
protected
speech.
They
cannot
be
reconciled
with
core
principles
of
the
First
Amendment.
If
the
state
governments
were
to
attempt
to
prohibit
ordinary
citizens
engaged
in
their
private
speech
activities
from
endorsing,
advocating,
or
promoting
the
same
substantive
ideas identified
in
the
anti-CRT
bills,
it
seems
evident
that
courts
would
regard
them
as
unconstitutional
under
current
First
Amendment
doctrine.
The
anti-
CRT
bills
are,
on
their
face,
regulations
of
speech
based
on
the
content
of
that
speech.
As
the
US
Supreme
Court
has
pointed
out,
a
long
line
of
modern
jurisprudence
has
emphasized
that
"above
all
else,
the
First
Amendment
means
that
government
has
no
power to
restrict
expression
because
of
its
message,
its
ideas,
its
subject
matter,
or
its
content."
1
As a
result,
"[c]ontent-based
regulations
are
presumptively
invalid."
2
Moreover,
"[w]hen
the
government
targets
not
subject
matter,
but
particular
views
taken
by
speakers
on
a
subject,
the
violation
of
the
First
Amendment
is
all
the
more
blatant."
3
The
First
Amendment,
"subject
only
to
narrow
and
well-understood
exceptions,
does
not
countenance
governmental
control
over
the
content
of
messages
expressed
by
private
individuals."
4
Promoting
divisive
concepts
does
not
fall
within
one
of
the
"narrow
and
well-understood
exceptions"
to
First
Amendment
protections,
nor
can
the
suppression
of
such
speech
be
expected
to
overcome
their
presumptive
invalidity.
5
Endorsing
the
belief
that
one
race
is
"inherently
superior"
to
another
or
that
members
of some
groups
should
receive
"adverse
treatment"
in
society
6
might
be
contrary
to
current
American
constitutional
commitments
and
public
values,
but
it
is
constitutionally
protected
political
expression.
7
1.
Police
Dep't
of
Chi.
v.
Mosley,
408
U.S.
92,
95
(1972).
2.
R.A.V.
v.
City
of
St.
Paul,
505
U.S.
377,
382
(1992).
3.
Rosenberger
v.
Rector
&
Visitors
of
the
Univ.
of
Va., 515
U.S.
819,
829
(1995).
4.
Turner
Broad.
Sys.,
Inc.
v.
FCC,
512
U.S.
622,
641
(1994).
5.
Id.
6.
See
infra
notes
42-43
and
accompanying
text.
7.
See,
e.g.,
Texas
v.
Johnson,
491
U.S.
397,
414
(1989)
("If
there
is
a
bedrock
principle
underlying
the
First
Amendment,
it
is
that
the
government
may
not
464
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
Although
one
might
think
that
"social
justice
ideology
poses
a
grave
threat
to
America
and
to
the
American
way
of
life,"
"teaches
students
to
hate
everything
that
makes
America
great,"
and
"divides
America
by
race,"
8
no
court
is
likely
to
accept
that
a
ban
on
the
expression
of
some
political
ideas
"is
justified
by
a compelling
government
interest
and
is
narrowly
drawn
to
serve
that
interest."
9
The
more
difficult
question
is
whether
professors
in
a
classroom
at
a
state
university
can
claim
similar
First
Amendment
protection.
If
a
state
were
to
prohibit
the
expression
of
such
ideas
by
a
private
citizen
in
a
public
park,
it
would
clearly
be
unconstitutional.
The
state
has
far
greater
leeway,
however,
in
regulating
the
speech
of
government
employees
when
they
are
performing
their
job
responsibilities.
10
When
subjecting
students
to
the
tenets
of
Critical
Race
Theory
in
the
classroom
of
a
state
university,
for
example,
are
professors
"speaking
as
citizens
for
First
Amendment
purposes"
or
are
they
subject
to
"employer
discipline"
if
the
state
government
objects
to
such
classroom
speech?
11
This
Article
argues
that
professorial
classroom
speech
should
be
regarded
as
constitutionally
protected
under
the
First
Amendment.
As
a
consequence,
state
legislatures
are
subject
to
significant
constitutional
limitations
in
attempting
to
suppress
such
speech.
12
Common
provisions
of
anti-CRT
bills
now
being
considered
by
state
legislatures
across
the
country
are
unconstitutional.
13
A
federal
judge
prohibit
the
expression
of
an
idea
simply
because
society
finds
the
idea
itself
offensive
or
disagreeable");
id.
at
418
("The
First
Amendment
does
not
guarantee
that
other
concepts
virtually
sacred
to
our
Nation
as
a
whole-such
as
the
principle
that
discrimination
on
the
basis
of
race
is
odious
and
destructive-will
go
unquestioned
in
the
marketplace
of
ideas.").
8.
H.R.
Con.
Res.
12,
66th
Leg.,
1st
Reg.
Sess.
(Idaho
2021).
9.
Brown
v.
Ent.
Merchs.
Ass'n,
564
U.S.
786,
799
(2011).
10.
Garcetti
v.
Ceballos,
547
U.S.
410,
418
(2006).
11.
Id.
at
421.
12.
I
do
not
address
in
this
Article
possible
due
process
concerns
arising
from
the
vagueness
of
these
proposals.
Such
concerns
are
real
given
how
many
of
these
bills
are
drafted,
but
at
least
in theory
statutory
language
could
be
improved
to
mitigate
such
problems.
The
First
Amendment
problem
would
remain
no
matter
how
well
drafted
the
bills
might
be.
13.
For
purposes
of
this
Article,
I
focus
on
the
individual
academic
freedom
of
university
professors.
I
lay
aside
alternative
arguments
that
might
be
grounded
in
what
is
sometimes
called
"institutional
academic
freedom"
(generally
understood
as the
freedom
of
the
educational
institution
to
pursue
its
mission
free
from
governmental
interference)
or
in
state
constitutional
provisions
securing
some
measure
of
independence
to
state
universities.
On
institutional
academic
freedom,
see
Matthew
W.
Finkin,
On
"Institutional"
Academic
Freedom,
61
TEX.
L.
REV.
817
(1983);
Mark
G.
Yudof,
Three
Faces
of Academic
Freedom,
32
LOY.
L.
REV.
831
(1987);
J.
Peter
Byrne,
Academic
Freedom:
A
"Special
Concern
of
the
First
Amendment,"
99
YALE
L.
J.
251
(1989);
David
M.
Rabban,
A
Functional
Analysis
of
"Individual"
and
"Institutional"
Academic
Freedom
under
the
First
Amendment,
53
LAw
&
CONTEMP.
PROBS.
227
(1990);
465
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
pointed out
some
time
ago, "To
suggest
that
the
First
Amendment,
as
a
matter
of
law,
is
never
implicated
when
a
professor
speaks
in
class,
is
fantastic."
14
Anti-CRT
policies
raise
novel
constitutional
problems
because
they
pose
the
most
aggressive
legislative
threat
to academic
freedom
in
decades,
but
it
would
be
fantastic
to
believe
that
established
First
Amendment
principles
would
not
extend
to
prohibiting
such
policies.
Even
a
fairly
modest
approach
to
recognizing
a
First
Amendment
interest
in
academic
freedom
should
be
sufficient
to
establish
the
constitutional
defects
with
the
current
legislative
proposals.
William
Van
Alstyne
once
contended,
"[A]cademic
freedom
is
a
special
subset
of
First
Amendment
freedoms."
15
Academic
freedom
is
not
a
freestanding
commitment
but
rather
protects
the
"peculiar
character
and
function
of
the
university
scholar."
16
It
is
the
particular
function
of
a
university
as
a
domain
of
free
inquiry
that
necessitates
protections
for
academic
freedom.
17
Given
the kind
of
modern
universities
that
have
been
constituted
in
the
United
States,
courts
have
recognized
that
the
academic
speech
that
takes
place
there
implicates
important
First
Amendment
values.
As
even
Chief
Justice
William
Rehnquist
noted,
"the
university
is
a
traditional
sphere
of
free
expression
so
fundamental
to
the
functioning
of
our
society
that
the
Government's
ability
to
control
speech
within
that
sphere"
is
constitutionally
limited.
18
By
attempting
to
suppress
university
classroom
speech
about
disfavored
ideas-and
more
particularly,
disfavored
viewpoints
about
contentious
social
issues-state
policymakers
are
impinging
on
First
Amendment
values
that
courts
can
and
should
protect.
Richard
H.
Hiers,
Institutional
Academic
Freedom
vs.
Faculty
Academic
Freedom
in
Public
Colleges
and
Universities:
A
Dubious
Dichotomy,
29
J.
COLL.
&
UNIV.
L.
35
(2002).
On
university
autonomy
under
state
constitutional
provisions,
see
Joseph
Beckham,
Reasonable
Independence
for
Public
Higher
Education:
Legal
Implications
of
Constitutionally
Autonomous
Status,
7
J.L.
&
EDUC.
177
(1978);
Caitlin
M.
Scully,
Note,
Autonomy
and
Accountability:
The
University
of
California
and
the
State
Constitution,
38
HASTINGS
L.J.
927
(1987);
Karen
Petroski,
Lessons
for
Academic
Freedom
Law:
The
California
Approach
to
University Autonomy
and
Accountability,
32
J.
COLL.
&
UNIV.
L.
149
(2005);
Neal
H.
Hutchens,
Preserving
the
Independence
of
Public
Higher
Education:
An
Examination
of
State
Constitutional
Autonomy
Provisions
for
Public
Colleges
and
Universities,
35
J.
COLL.
&
UNIV.
L.
271
(2009).
14.
Scallet
v.
Rosenblum,
911
F.
Supp.
999,
1013-14
(W.D.
Va.
1996).
15.
William
W.
Van
Alstyne,
The
Specific
Theory
of
Academic
Freedom
and
the
General
Issue
of
Civil
Liberties,
404
ANNALS
AM.
ACAD.
POL.
&
Soc.
Sc.
140,
143 (1972).
16.
Id.
at
142.
17.
See
Robert
C.
Post, The
Classic
First
Amendment
Tradition
Under
Stress:
Freedom
of
Speech
and
the
University,
in
THE
FREE
SPEECH
CENTURY
106,
121
(Lee
C.
Bollinger
&
Geoffrey
R.
Stone
eds.,
2019).
18.
Rust
v.
Sullivan,
500
U.S.
173,
200
(1991).
466
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
In
Part
I,
I
review
the
current
legislative
efforts
to
restrict
speech
about
race
in
higher
education.
This
review
will
reveal
the
scope
of
the
problem
and
the
common
speech
restrictions
now
being
contemplated
by
state
officials.
In
Part
II,
I
briefly
survey
an
earlier
legislative
effort
to
restrict
professorial
speech.
The
concerted
effort
to
stamp
out
"radical"
and
"subversive"
ideas
on
college
campuses
in
the
mid-twentieth
century
helped
create
the
First
Amendment
jurisprudence
on
academic
freedom.
In
Part
III,
I
outline
the
relationship
between
the
First
Amendment
and
principles
of
academic
freedom
with
a
particular
focus
on
elaborating
how
best
to
think
about
constitutional
protections
for
professorial
classroom
speech.
In
Part
IV,
I
examine
what
the
US
Supreme
Court
has
said
about
government-employee
speech
and
how
it
relates
to
academic
freedom.
The
Court
has
left
unclear
the
scope
of
constitutional
academic-freedom
protections
in
that
context,
and
I
argue
that
the
principles
that
have
been
articulated
by
the
justices
over
time
are
best
resolved
by
more
clearly
recognizing
robust
constitutional
protections
in
this
context.
In
doing
so,
I
will
clarify
the
extent
to
which
professorial
speech
ought
to
be
constitutionally
protected
from
legislative
interference
in
three
distinct
but
important
contexts:
classroom
speech,
scholarly
speech,
and
purely
private
speech.
In
Part
V,
I
examine
the
Court's
jurisprudence
on
distinguishing
between
governmental
and
private
speech
in
spaces
where
the
government
is
heavily
involved,
like
a
state-university
campus.
I
argue
that
professorial
classroom
speech
should
not
be
understood
to
be
a
form
of
government
speech
that
can
be
properly
regulated
by
government
officials.
I.
THE
CULTURE
WAR
AND
ANTI-CRITICAL
RACE
THEORY
LEGISLATION
With
remarkable
speed,
policymakers
across
the
country
have
focused
their
attention
on
what
are
sometimes
characterized
as
"divisive
concepts."
19
President
Donald
Trump
got
the
ball
rolling
when
he
issued
an
executive
order
at
the
beginning
of
the
2020
electoral
campaign
season
seeking
to
root
out
"divisive
concepts"
in
the
federal
government.
20
His
executive
order
identified
a
list
of
concepts,
including
such
claims
as
that
the
"United
States
is
fundamentally
racist"
and
that
"any
individual
should
feel
discomfort,
guilt,
anguish,
or
any
form
of
psychological
distress
on
account
of
his
or
her
race
or
sex,"
that
should
be
purged
from
federal
employee
training.
21
Soon,
Republican
legislators
across
the
country
19.
Sarah
Schwartz,
Map:
Where
Critical
Race
Theory
is
Under
Attack,
EDWEEK
(Feb.
3,
2023),
https://www.edweek.org/policy-politics/map-where-
critical-race-theory-is-under-attack/2021/06.
20.
Exec.
Order
No.
13950,
3
C.F.R.
§
433
(2021).
21.
Id.
at
§
436.
467
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
were
rushing
to
introduce
bills
that
were
similarly
aimed
at
divisive
concepts
in
state
government.
2
2
Unlike
Trump's
executive
order,
however,
many
of
these
state-level
bills
were
aimed
at
educational
institutions.
The
first
wave
of
bills
generally
focused
on
primary
and
secondary
schools.
23
An
emerging
wave
has
taken
greater
aim
at
higher
education.
24
22.
Char
Adams,
How
Trump
Ignited
the
Fight
over
Critical
Race
Theory
in
Schools,
NBC
NEWS
(May
10,
2021,
6:05
AM),
https://www.nbcnews.com/news/nbcblk/how-trump-ignited-fight-over-critical-
race-theory-schools-n1266701.
23.
Peter
Greene,
Teacher
Anti-CRT
Bills
Coast
to
Coast:
A
State
by
State
Guide,
FORBES
(Feb.
16,
2022,
2:00
PM),
https://www.forbes.com/sites/petergreene/2022/02/16/teacher-anti-crt-bills-coast-
to-coast-a-state-by-state-guide/;
Rashawn
Ray
&
Alexandra
Gibbons,
Why
Are
States
Banning
Critical
Race
Theory?,
BROOKINGs
(Nov.
21,
2021),
https://www.brookings.edublog/fixgov/2021/07/02/why-are-states-banning-
critical-race-theory/.
This
Article
brackets
the
policy
and
constitutional
questions
surrounding
the
anti-CRT
bills
aimed
at
primary
and
secondary
education,
where
arguably
the
government's
role
as
a
speaker
is
much
stronger
and
the
teacher's
First
Amendment
interests
in
the
classroom
are
much weaker.
I
contend
that,
for
First
Amendment
purposes,
professorial
speech
at
the
university
level
should
be
distinguished
from
teacher
speech
at
the
primary
and
secondary
school
level
and
that
analogizing
university
classrooms
to
secondary
school
classrooms
is
largely
inapt.
Universities
are
importantly
sites
of
free
inquiry
on
the
boundaries
of
human
knowledge.
Fulfilling
such
a
mission
of
advancing
knowledge
requires
greater
freedom
for exploring
controversial
ideas.
Universities
are
not
about
socializing
children into
a
community's
values
but
about
challenging
adults
to
think
about
difficult
ideas.
Both
state
universities
and
public
schools
have
an
educational
mission,
but
the
nature
of
that
mission
is
quite
different.
See,
e.g.,
Mayer
v.
Monroe
Cnty.
Cmty.
Sch.
Corp.,
474
F.3d
477,
479
(7th
Cir.
2007) ("[T]he
school
system
does
not
'regulate'
teachers'
speech
as
much
as
it
hires
that
speech.
Expression
is
a
teacher's
stock
in
trade,
the
commodity
she
sells
to
her
employer
in
exchange
for
a
salary.
A
teacher
hired
to
lead
a
social-studies
class
can't
use
it
as a
platform
for
a
revisionist
perspective
that
Benedict
Arnold
wasn't
really
a
traitor,
when
the
approved
program
calls
him
one.");
Boring
v.
Buncombe
Cnty.
Bd.
of
Educ.,
136
F.3d
364, 371
(4th
Cir.
1998)
("Someone
must
fix
the
curriculum
of
any
school,
public
or
private.
In
the
case
of
a
public
school,
in
our
opinion,
it
is
far
better
public
policy,
absent
a
valid
statutory
directive
on
the
subject,
that
the
makeup
of
the
curriculum
be
entrusted
to
the
local
school
authorities
who
are
in
some
sense
responsible,
rather
than
to
the
teachers,
who
would
be
responsible
only
to
the
judges,
had
they
a
First
Amendment
right
to
participate
in
the
makeup
of
the
curriculum.");
Kirkland
v.
Northside
Indep.
Sch.
Dist.,
890
F.2d
794,
800
(5th
Cir.
1989)
("Although,
the
concept
of
academic
freedom
has
been
recognized
in
our
jurisprudence,
the
doctrine
has
never
conferred
upon
teachers
the
control
of
public
school
curricula.").
24.
Wyatt
Myskow,
Legislation
to
Limit
Critical
Race
Theory
at
Colleges
Has
Reached
Fever
Pitch,
CHRON.
HIGHER
EDUC.
(June
8,
2022),
https://www.chronicle.com/article/legislation-to-limit-critical-race-theory-at-
colleges-has-reached-fever-pitch.
468
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
These
bills
have
become
more
popularly
known
as
anti-CRT
legislation.
In
a
strict
academic
sense,
Critical
Race
Theory
is
a
body
of
literature
that
has
emphasized
the
routine
prevalence
of
racism,
often
subtle
and
institutionalized,
in
contemporary
American
society.
25
In
a
legal
context,
that
work
has
emphasized
the
inadequacy
of
the
civil
rights
efforts
of
the
mid-twentieth
century
and
the
need
for
a
transformation
of
civil
rights
thinking
and
law.
26
Although
Critical
Race
Theory
may
have
gotten
its
start
in
the
law
schools,
it
has
had
an
enormous
impact
in
the
field
of
education
as
well.
27
Developing
an
"analogous"
mode
of
analysis,
this
literature
has
emphasized
the
importance
of
racism
and
capitalism
as
the
drivers
of
educational
inequities.
28
A
self-consciously
activist
literature,
it
has
sought
to
train
teachers
to
uproot
"normative
whiteness"
and
"a
system
of
achievement
premised
on
competition."
29
Such
scholarly
enterprises
might
have
been
little
known
outside
their
immediate
environments,
but
they
gained
new
prominence
in
the
wake
of
the
Black
Lives
Matters
protests
during
the
summer
of
2020.
In
particular,
Christopher
Rufo
of
the
Manhattan
Institute,
a
conservative
think
tank,
is
generally
credited
with
giving
the
term
political
salience.
30
Rufo
called
attention
to
the
growing
popularity
of
employee
training,
including
in
government
agencies,
aimed
at
ferreting
out
"whiteness."
31
Infamously,
Rufo
laid
out
his
rhetorical
strategy
in
public
via
Twitter:
"The
goal
is
to
have
the
public
read
something
crazy
in
the
newspaper
and
immediately
think
'critical
25.
See,
e.g.,
CRITICAL
RACE
THEORY:
THE
KEY
WRITINGS
THAT
FORMED
THE
MOVEMENT
(Kimberl6
Crenshaw
et
al.
eds.,
1995);
Richard
Delgado
&
Jean
Stefancic,
CRITICAL
RACE
THEORY:
AN
INTRODUCTION
3
(3d
ed.
2017).
26.
See,
e.g.,
Derick
A.
Bell,
Jr.,
Comment,
Brown
v.
Board
of
Education
and
the
Interest-Convergence
Dilemma,
93
HARV.
L.
REV.
518
(1980);
Kimberl6
Williams
Crenshaw,
Race,
Reform,
and
Retrenchment:
Transformation
and
Legitimation
in
Antidiscrimination
Law,
101
HARV.
L.
REV.
1331
(1988);
MARI
J.
MATSUDA
ET
AL.,
WORDS
THAT
WOUND
(1993).
27.
See,
e.g.,
HANDBOOK
OF
CRITICAL
RACE
THEORY
IN
EDUCATION
(2d
ed.
Marvin
Lynn
&
Adrienne
D.
Dixson
eds.
2022).
28.
Gloria
Ladson-Billings
&
William
F.
Tate
IV,
Toward
a
Critical
Race
Theory
of
Education,
97
TCHRS.
COLL.
REC.
47,
47 (1995).
29.
Adrienne
D.
Dixson
&
Celia
Rousseau
Anderson,
Where
are
We?
Critical
Race
Theory
in
Education
20
Years
Later,
93
PEABODY
J.
OF
EDUC.
121,
122
(2018).
30.
Christopher
F.
Rufo,
"White
Fragility"
Comes
to
Washington,
CITY
J.
(July
18,
2020),
https://www.city-journal.org/white-fragility-comes-to-
washington.
31.
Adam
Harris,
The
GOP's
'Critical
Race
Theory'
Obsession,
ATL.
(May
7,
2021),
https://www.theatlantic.com/politics/archive/2021/05/gops-critical-race-
theory-fixation-explained/618828/;
Laura
Meckler
&
Josh
Dawsey,
Republicans,
Spurred
by
an
Unlikely
Figure,
See
Political
Promise
in
Targeting
Critical
Race
Theory,
WASH.
POST
(June
21,
2021,
6:22
PM),
https://www.washingtonpost.com/education/2021/06/19/critical-race-theory-rufo-
republicans/.
469
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
race
theory."'
32
The
plan
seems
to
have
worked.
Lots
of
things
were
soon
lumped
under
the
label,
and
"critical
race theory"
became
a
catch-all,
if
dimly
understood,
way
for
conservatives
to
describe
racial
ideas
and
arguments
that
they
did
not
like.
As a
result,
the
anti-CRT
proposals
have
only
a
loose
connection
to
the
academic
literature
known
as Critical
Race
Theory.
This
development
generates
confusion
and
obfuscation
but
has
little
substantive
consequence.
33
For
purposes
of
this
Article,
"critical
race
theory"
can
be
understood
to
have
implicit
scare
quotes
as
it
refers
to
this
political
debate
rather
than
to
the
scholarly
literature.
The
policies
in
play
would
be
no
better
or
worse from
an
academic-freedom
perspective
if
they
were
aimed
more
accurately
at
a
particular
scholarly
movement
or
literature.
Of
more
immediate
significance,
the attack
on
Critical
Race
Theory
quickly
moved
beyond
employee
training
sessions
to
the
school
curriculum.
President
Trump's
divisive-concepts
executive
order
served
as
a
model
for
state
and
local
policymaking
activity in
subsequent
months.
34
Arizona
prohibited
state
agencies
from
making
use
of
employee
training
that
"presents
any
form
of
blame
or
judgment
on
the basis
of
race,
ethnicity,
or
sex."
35
Georgia
adopted
the
Protect
Students
First
Act,
which
prohibited
"classroom
instruction"
that
"advocate[s]
for
divisive
concepts."
Among
those
divisive
concepts
are
the
claims
that
individuals
should
feel
anguish
or
guilt
"by
virtue
of
his
or
her
race"
and
that
"recognition
and
appreciation
of
character
traits
such
as
a
hard
work
ethic
are
racist."
36
North
Dakota
required
that
the
public-school
curriculum
be
"factual"
and
"objective"
and
"not
include
instruction
relating
to
critical
race
theory."
37
South
Carolina
included
a
budget
rider
on
"partisanship
curriculum"
that
prohibited
curricula,
textbooks,
or
instructional
materials
that
"serve
to
inculcate"
various
disfavored
32.
Christopher
F.
Rufo
(@realchrisrufo),
TWITTER
(Mar.
15,
2021,
3:17
PM),
https://twitter.com/realchrisrufo/status/1371541044592996352?lang=en.
33.
Some
legislative
proposals
are
substantively
affected
by
the
confusion
to
the
extent
that
they
are
vague
about
exactly
what
speech
is
being
banned,
but
most
of
the
proposals
do
not
attempt
to
ban
"critical
race
theory"
as
such
but
instead
delineate
a
set
of
more
specific
ideas
that
should
not
be
discussed.
Many
of
the
proposals
still
have
vagueness
problems,
but
not
as
a
result
of
confusion
of
the
meaning
of
"critical
race
theory."
On
the
lack
of
clarity
in
the
anti-CRT
bills,
see
Keith Whittington,
The
Trouble
with
Banning
Critical
Race
Theory,
AREO
(June
16,
2021),
https://areomagazine.com/2021/06/16/the-trouble-with-banning-
critical-race-theory/.
34.
JONATHAN
FRIEDMAN
&
JAMES
TAGER,
EDUCATIONAL
GAG
ORDERS
25-26
(2022);
Whittington,
supra
note
33.
35.
H.B.
2906,
55th
Leg.,
1st
Reg.
Sess.
(Ariz. 2021).
36. H.B.
1084,
2022 Leg.,
Reg.
Sess.
(Ga.
2022).
37.
H.B.
1508,
67th
Leg.,
Spec.
Sess.
(N.D. 2021).
470
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
concepts.
3
8
Texas
adopted
a
civics
training
program
that
included
a
prohibited
list
of
divisive
concepts.
39
With
the
ink
barely
dry
on
policies
focused
on
primary
and
secondary
education,
legislators
began
to
advance
similar
bills
focused
on
higher
education.
A
small
number
have
passed
into
law,
but
many
more
are
in
the
pipeline.
The
various
proposals
have
many
commonalities,
but
they
are
not
all
the
same.
Some
examples
will
indicate
the
challenges
posed
by
such
legislation.
The
common
theme
is
that
they
all
burden
professorial
speech
in
the
classroom
by
restricting
the
topics
and
perspectives
that
a
professor
may
discuss
or
advance
while
performing
his
or
her
instructional
duties.
Perhaps
the
most
high-profile
of
the
bills
signed
into
law
is
Florida's
so-called
"Stop
WOKE
Act,"
or
House
Bill
7.
Passed
with
great
fanfare
at
the
behest
of
the
governor's
office,
Florida
Republican
Governor
Ron
DeSantis
declared
that
"we
will
not
let
the
far-left
woke
agenda
take
over
our
schools"
and
that
"there
is
no
place
for
indoctrination"
in
the
state.
40
A
key
feature
of
the
law
echoes
other
divisive-concepts
proposals.
It
declares
it
to
be
prohibited
"discrimination
on
the
basis
of
race"
for
any
student
in
the
state
to
be
exposed
to
"training
or
instruction
that
espouses,
promotes,
advances,
inculcates,
or
compels
such
student
..
.
to
believe
any"
of
a
list
of
concepts,
including
that
members
of
one
race
are
"morally
superior"
to
members
of
another;
that
a
person's
"status"
is
"either
privileged
or
oppressed"
as
a
result
of
their
race
or
sex;
that
a
person
"should
be
discriminated
against
or
receive
adverse
treatment
to
achieve
diversity,
equity,
or
inclusion;"
or
that
"such
virtues
as
merit,
excellence,
hard
work,
fairness,
objectivity,
and
racial
colorblindness
are
racist
or
sexist."
4
1
The
discussion
of
such
concepts
is
not
prohibited
so
long
as
they
are
"part
of
a
larger
course
of
training
or
instruction"
and
such
instruction
"is
given
in
an
objective
manner
without
endorsement
of
the
concepts."
42
By
prohibiting
university
instruction
that
"espouses,"
"promotes,"
"advances,"
or
offers
with
"endorsement"
such
concepts,
the
state
restricts
ordinary
academic
discourse
in
a
range
of
disciplines
and
hampers
the
ability
of
38.
H.B.
4100,
124th
Gen.
Assemb.,
Reg.
Sess.
(S.C.
2022).
39.
S.B.
3,
87th
Leg.,
Reg.
Sess.
(Tex.
2021).
40.
John
Kennedy,
DeSantis'
'Stop
WOKE
Act'
Faces
Court
Test
as
Universities
Become
Targets.
At
Issue:
Free
Speech,
FLA.
TIMES-UNION
(June
19,
2022,
6:05
PM),
https://www.jacksonville.com/story/news/politics/2022/06/16/desantis-florida-
stop-woke-act-challenged-universities-free-speech/
7 6
3
00
3 3
001/.
41.
H.B.
7,
2022
Leg.,
Reg.
Sess.
(Fla.
2022);
FLA.
STAT.
§
1000.05(4)(a)
(2022).
42.
FLA.
STAT.
§
1000.05(4)(b)
(2022).
471
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
professors
to
construct
ordinary
political
and
policy
arguments
relating
to
a
variety
of
disputed
issues
involving
race
and
sex.
4 3
The
Idaho
anti-CRT
statute
makes
direct
reference
to
"tenets
.
. .
often
found
in
'critical
race
theory"'
in
its
new
legislation
on
"dignity
and
nondiscrimination
in
public
education."
44
Because
the
legislature
regards
such
concepts
as
likely
to
"exacerbate
and
inflame
divisions,"
it
prohibits
any
"public
institution
of
higher
education"
from
directing
or
compelling
students
"to
personally
affirm,
adopt,
or
adhere
to"
a
list
of
tenets,
including
that
a
race
or sex
is
inherently
superior
to
another,
that
individuals
should
be
adversely
treated
on
the
basis
of
such
characteristics,
or
that
individuals
are
"inherently
responsible"
for
actions
committed
in
the
past
by
other
individuals
who
share
such
characteristics.4
5
This
legislation
has
a
far
narrower
scope
than
other
versions
of
divisive-concepts
bills
since
it
does
not
prohibit
mere
advocacy
or
promotion
of
such
ideas
by
instructors
but
only
compelling
students
to
"personally
affirm"
them.
46
Other
proposals
that
have
been
advanced
in
the
Idaho
legislature
but
not
yet
adopted
into
law
are
more
sweeping.
A
House
concurrent
resolution
declared
that
"universities
should
eliminate
courses
.
.
.
that
are
infused
with
social
justice
ideology"
and
threatened
future
cuts
in
state
funding
to
universities
that
failed
to
do
so.4
7
House
Bill
352
takes
a
broader
approach
to
banning
divisive
concepts
from
university
classrooms.
It
would
prohibit
a
list
of
"racist
or
sexist
concept[s]"
and
bar
professors
at
public
universities
from
"teach[ing],"
"advocat[ing],
or
"encourage[ing]
the
adoption"
of
such
concepts
"while
instructing
students."
48
Universities
would
be
further
barred
from
hosting
speakers
who
advocate
such
positions
or
43.
The
Stop
WOKE
Act
has
been
enjoined
by
a
federal
district
court.
Novoa
v.
Diaz,
No.
4:22-cv-00324-MW/MAF
(N.D.
Fla.
2022)
(Court
Listener).
44.
IDAHO
CODE
§
33-138(2)
(2021).
45.
IDAHO
CODE
§
33-138(3)(a)
(2021).
46.
What
counts
as
"personally
affirming"
a
tenet
of
critical
race
theory
might
still
create
mischief
in
an
educational
setting,
however.
Compelled
speech
is
constitutionally
disfavored.
As
Justice
Robert
Jackson
noted
in
the
flag-salute
case,
it
is
not
"open
to
public
authorities
to
compel
[an
individual]
to
utter
what
is
not in
his
mind."
W.
Va.
State
Bd.
of
Educ.
v.
Barnette,
319
U.S.
624,
634
(1943).
It
is
clear
that
what
concerned
the
Court
was
compelling
a
certain
"attitude
of
mind"
and
forcing
individuals
to
"confess
by
word
or
act
their
faith"
in
government
prescribed
orthodoxies.
Id.
at
633,
642.
But
it
is
also
familiar
that
in
an
educational
context
students
might
well
be
asked
to
express
"words
without
belief'
in
the
context
of
a
debate
or
an
examination
in
ways
that
do
not
look
like
the
kind
of
"prescribed
ceremony"
at
stake
in
the
flag-salute
context.
Id.
at
633.
If
the
statute
is
read
narrowly
to
apply
to forced
expressions
of
belief
comparable
to
reciting
the
Pledge
of
Allegiance,
then
it
would
avoid
such
pitfalls
and
reaffirm
the constitutional
right
that
students
already
possess
to
be
free
from
compelled
speech.
47.
H.R.
12,
66th
Leg.,
1st
Reg.
Sess.
(Idaho
2021).
48.
H.B.
352,
66th
Leg.,
1st
Reg.
Sess.
(Idaho
2021).
472
[Vol.
58
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
the
"1619
Project"
in
its
curriculum.
57
The
Iowa
bill
is
one
of
several
legislative
proposals
in
multiple
states
aimed
at
banning
the
1619
Project
from
public
school
or
public
university
classrooms.
58
Measures
introduced
in
Oklahoma
and
Missouri
would
cut
state
funds
to
any
universities
using
the
materials.
5
9
A
separate
Missouri
bill
would
have
imposed
similar
financial
penalties
on
any
state
university
that
adopted
a
"curriculum
implementing
critical
race
theory"
or
taught
"components
of
critical
race
theory
as
part
of
any
curriculum,
course
syllabus,
or
instruction
in
any
course
or
program
of
study."
60
A
New
York
bill
would
have
prohibited
requiring
college
students
to
"study
the
1619
Project"
or
taking
a
course
that
"teaches
individuals
to
feel
discomfort
...
due
to
the
individual's
race
or
religion."
61
Others
would
bring
the
divisive-concepts
bans
into
college-level
teaching.
A
bill
introduced
in
Alabama
directed
that
no
university
professor
shall
"teach"
anything
on
a
list
of
divisive
concepts.
6
2
A
bill
in
Arkansas
would
have
barred
university
professors
from
"promot[ing]"
"social
justice"
or
"division
between"
races,
genders,
social
classes,
or
political
groups.
6 3
A
bill
in
Kentucky
with
the
straightforward
title
of
"an
act
relating
to
prohibited
instruction"
would
have
mandated
that
no
student
"be
subjected
to
any
classroom
instruction
or
discussion"
or
"textbooks
and
instructional
materials"
that
promote
a
divisive
concept.
64
A
similar
measure
in
South
Carolina
would
have
likewise
freed
college
students
from
"ideological
coercion
and
indoctrination"
by
banning
delineated
"discriminatory
concepts"
from
any
"instruction,
presentations,
discussions,
or
counseling."
65
The
"Teaching
Racial
and
Universal
Equality
(TRUE)
Act"
in
Mississippi
would
have
prohibited
including
"divisive
concepts
as
part
of
a course
of
instruction
or
in
a
curriculum
or
instructional
program"
at
a
state
university.
66
Its
list
of
divisive
concepts
was
a
bit
more
expansive
than
most,
including
on
the
list
of
prohibited
ideas
57.
H.B.
222, 2021
Leg.
(Iowa
2021).
58.
Sarah
Schwartz,
Lawmakers
Push
to
Ban
"1619
Project"
from
Schools,
EDUC.
WEEK
(Feb.
3,
2021),
https://www.edweek.org/teaching-
learning/lawmakers-push-to-ban-1619-project-from-schools/2021/02;
Barbara
Rodriguez,
Republican
State
Lawmakers
Want
to
Punish
Schools
that
Teach
the
1619
Project,
USA
TODAY
(Feb.
10,
2021,
11:39
AM),
https://www.usatoday.com/story/news/education/2021/02/10/slavery-and-history-
states-threaten-funding-schools-teach-1619-project/4454195001/.
59.
H.B.
2988,
58th
Leg.,
2d
Sess.
(Okla.
2022);
H.B.
952,
101st
Gen.
Assemb.,
1st
Reg.
Sess.
(Mo.
2021).
60.
H.B.
1634,
101st
Gen.
Assemb.,
2d
Reg.
Sess.
(Mo.
2021).
61.
A.B.
8253,
2021
Leg.,
Reg.
Sess.
(N.Y.
2021).
62.
H.B.
9,
2021
Leg.,
Reg.
Sess.
(Ala.
2022).
63.
H.B.
1218,
93d
Gen.
Assemb.,
Reg.
Sess.
(Ark.
2021).
64.
H.B.
18,
2022
Leg.,
Reg.
Sess.
(Ky.
2022).
65.
H.B.
4605,
2021
Gen.
Assemb.,
124th
Sess.
(S.C.
2021).
66.
H.B.
437,
2022
Leg.,
Reg.
Sess.
(Miss.
2022).
474
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
that
"capitalism"
or
"free
markets"
"are
racist
and
sexist
or
oppress
a
given
race
or
sex"
and
ideas
that
promote
"the
violent
overthrow
of
the
United
States
government."
67
A
New
Hampshire
bill
would
have
simply
extended
its
divisive-concepts
law
that
applied
to
state
employee
training
68
to
include
university
classroom
instruction.
6
9
Pennsylvania
would
have
prohibited
professors
from
"teach[ing]"
or
"advocat[ing]"
a
divisive
concept
"while
instructing
students."
70
To
date,
legislative
proposals
relating
to
divisive
concepts
in
higher
education
have
focused
on
training
sessions
and
classroom
instruction.
They
have
proposed
regulating
college
curricula,
banning
instructional
materials,
and
curtailing
classroom
discussions.
We
are
still
in
the
early
stages
of
the
anti-CRT
movement,
however.
It
is
not
hard
to
imagine
state
government
officials
setting
their
sights
on
other
expression
of
such
disfavored
ideas
by
state-university
professors
in
other
contexts.
In
addition
to
classroom
speech,
professors
routinely
speak
in
two
other
contexts
that
traditional
academic-freedom
policies
and
principles
have
also
tried
to
protect.
71
Scholarly
speech
in
the
form
of
presentations
in
scholarly
venues
and
publication
of
scholarly
research
might
not
directly
involve
students,
but
it
can
certainly
develop
and
promote
the
same
disfavored
ideas
targeted
by
the
current
divisive-concepts
proposals.
It
would
not
be
hard
to
imagine
policymakers
attempting
to
likewise
suppress
scholarship
that
might
be
characterized
as
"racist."
72
Professors
also
engage
in
private
speech,
or
what
in
the
academic-freedom
context
is
characterized
as
"extramural
speech."
7
3
It
is
not
at
all
obvious
that
politicians
concerned
with
divisive
and
dangerous
ideas
being
promoted
by
state-university
professors
will
limit
their
attention
to
what
those
professors
say
in
the
classroom.
74
67.
Id.
68.
H.B.
544,
2021
Gen.
Ct.,
Reg.
Sess.
(N.H.
2021).
69.
H.B.
1313,
2022
Gen.
Ct.,
Reg.
Sess.
(N.H.
2022).
70.
H.B.
1532,
2021
Gen.
Assemb.,
Reg.
Sess.
(Pa.
2021).
71.
See
infra
text
accompanying
notes
113-14.
72.
Indeed,
such
proposals
are
already
on
the
table
but
with
a
different
political
valence.
Many
of
my
colleagues
at
Princeton
University
have
urged
the
university
to
carve
out
an
exception
from
academic-freedom
protections
for
"racist"
scholarship.
Only
modest
tinkering
would
be
needed
to
make
such
proposals
serve
the
goals
of
the
politicians
currently
advancing
bills
aimed
at
"discriminatory
concepts."
Keith
Whittington,
Chipping
Away
at
Academic
Freedom,
REAL
CLEAR
POL.
(Aug.
23,
2020),
https://www.realclearpolitics.com/articles/2020/08/23/chipping_awayatacadem
ic_freedom_144012.html.
73.
Keith
E.
Whittington,
Academic
Freedom
and
the
Scope
of
Protections
for
Extramural
Speech,
105
ACADEME
20,
22
(2019).
74.
In
fact,
the
extramural
speech
of
professors
frequently
generates
political
controversy,
though
these
efforts
to
sanction
faculty
for
unpopular
things
that
they
have
said
in
public
are
more
often
ad
hoc
than
systematic.
See,
e.g.,
Keith
E.
Whittington,
Protecting
Extramural
Speech,
AcADEME
BLOC
(Feb.
15,
2019),
475
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
A
trustee
at
a
state
university
in
Florida
recently
complained
that
they
should
be more
involved
in
faculty
tenure
decisions
and
would
need
more
information
in
order
to
make
such
decisions.
75
Governor-
appointed
board
members
needed
to
know
about
a
professor's
"viewpoints,
about
his
research,
about
his
political
affiliations
or
potential
donations."
76
The
powerful
lieutenant
governor
of
Texas
has
called
for new
legislation
specifying
that
"teaching
Critical
Race
Theory"
would
be
a
"cause
for
a
tenured
professor
to
be
dismissed,"
while
seeking
to
shift
faculty
to
annual
"tenure
reviews"
in
order
to
remain
employed.
77
If
professors
spouting
"nonsense"
is
a
good
reason
for
government
officials
to
get
rid
of
them,
it
seems
unlikely
that
the
only
nonsense
that
will
matter
is
that
being
expressed
in
the
classroom.
78
Problematic
bills
get
introduced
into
state
legislatures
all
the
time.
Given
the
number
of
state
legislators
in
the
country,
it
is
not
hard
to
engage
in
an
exercise
of
"nutpicking"
to
feed
worries
about
ill-
conceived
legislative
proposals
with
little
chance
of
adoption
or
influence.
Unfortunately,
there
is
more
substantial
cause
for
concern
regarding
the
anti-CRT
bills.
The
first
wave
of
divisive-concepts
bills
already
yielded
some
legislative
success,
and
their
advocates
have
only
just
started
to
turn
their
attention
to
higher
education.
The
volume
and
prominence
of
legislative
proposals
looking
to
restrict
what
can
be
included
in
the
curriculum
of
state
universities
cannot
be
easily
dismissed
as political
longshots.
Universities
have
already
begun
to
react
to
the
new
political
environment
by
seeking
to
curtail
https://academeblog.org/2019/02/15/protecting-extramural-speech/;
Keith
E.
Whittington,
Extramural
Speech
at
Auburn,
VOLOKH
CONsPIRACY
(Aug.
3,
2020,
9:52
PM),
https://reason.com/volokh/2020/08/03/extramural-speech-at-auburn/;
Keith
E.
Whittington,
Controversial
Researcher
Driven
from
Campus
at
Old
Dominion
University,
VOLOKH
CONSPIRACY
(Dec.
1,
2021,
11:10
AM),
https://reason.com/volokh/2021/12/01/controversial-researcher-driven-from-
campus-at-old-dominion-university/;
Keith
E.
Whittington,
A
State
Attorney
General
Demands
that
a
Professor
be
Held
'Accountable"
for
a
Tweet,
VoLoKH
CONSPIRACY
(Dec.
11,
2021,
12:52
PM),
https://reason.com/volokh/2021/12/11/a-
state-attorney-general-demands-that-a-professor-be-held-accountable-for-a-
tweet/.
75.
Colleen
Flaherty,
Having
Their
Say-and
Then
Some,
INSIDE
HIGHER
ED
(May
17,
2021),
https://www.insidehighered.com/news/2021/05/17/trustees-
florida-atlantic-want-play-role-faculty-tenure-process.
76.
Id.
77.
Lt.
Gov.
Dan
Patrick,
State
of
Texas,
Statement
on
Plans
for
Higher
Education
and
Tenure,
LIEUTENANT
Gov.
TEX.
(Feb.
18,
2022),
https://www.ltgov.texas.gov/2022/02/18/lt-gov-dan-patrick-statement-on-plans-
for-higher-education-and-tenure/.
78.
Kate
McGee,
Lt.
Gov.
Dan
Patrick
Proposes
Ending
University
Tenure
to
Combat
Critical
Race
Theory
Teachings,
TEX.
TRIB.
(Feb.
18,
2022,
12:00
PM),
https://www.texastribune.org/2022/02/18/dan-patrick-texas-tenure-critical-race-
theory/.
476
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
programmatic
and
instructional
activities
that
might
incense
state
politicians.
79
While
it
is
certainly
too
early
to
predict
what
form
restrictions
might
take,
it
is
not
too
early
to
begin
to
grapple
with
the
constitutional
issues
that
such
proposals
raise.
The
possibility
of
legislative
restrictions
on
state-university
classroom
teaching
has
moved
from
the
world
of
idle
hypotheticals
to
the
political
mainstream.
80
II.
THE
COLD
WAR
AND
ANTI-SUBVERSIVE
LEGISLATION
The
current
political
assault
on
state
universities
is
perhaps
the
most
substantial
since
the
early
days
of
the
Cold
War.
It
remains
to
be
seen
whether
the
current
political
efforts
will
be
as
consequential
as
those
of
the
mid-twentieth
century,
but
political
interest
in
speech
activities
on
college
campuses
is
higher
now
than
it
has
been
in
decades.
The
search
for
"subversives"
in
the
postwar
period
sought
to
suppress
radical
ideas
in
public
and
private
institutions
of
higher
education.
81
The
current
wave
of
anti-CRT
legislation
has
similar
goals.
The
anti-subversive
legislation
of
the
Cold
War
era
spurred
the
Supreme
Court
to
begin
to
constitutionalize
academic-freedom
principles.
8
2
The
anti-CRT
legislation
could
prod
the
Court
to
push
those
developments
further.
79.
See,
e.g.,
Mike
Schneider,
Florida
Professors
Cite
Fear
of
State
Politicians
on
Campus,
AP
(Dec.
7,
2021),
https://apnews.comlarticle/coronavirus-pandemic-
health-education-florida-censorship-3eb326e17c91077ae1fe7d5b45fldf89;
Frequently
Asked
Questions:
Iowa
House
File
802,
IOWA
STATE
UNIV.
(Aug.
5,
2021),
https://www.provost.iastate.edu/policies/iowa-house-file-
80
2
---
requirements-related-to-racism-and-sexism-trainings.
80.
It
should
be
noted
that
this
Article
focuses
on
legislative
restrictions
on
classroom
teaching
in universities,
but
the
current
threat
to
academic
freedom
in
public
universities
is
broader.
Significant
alteration
in
the
tenure
system
has
been
proposed
in
several
states
and
politically
appointed
boards
of
trustees
in
public
university
systems
have
toyed
with
the
idea
of
becoming
more
interventionist
in
the
academic
affairs
of
the
universities
they
oversee.
Keith
E.
Whittington,
The
Intellectual
Freedom
that
Made
Public
Colleges
Great
is
Under
Threat,
WASH.
PosT
(Dec.
15,
2021,
6:00
AM),
https://www.washingtonpost.com/outlook/
2
0
2
1/12/15/academic-freedom-crt-
public-universities/.
Private
universities
are
facing
their
own
academic-freedom
challenges
as
well.
Keith
E.
Whittington,
Free
Speech
is
Under
Threat
on
College
Campuses.
Here's
How
to
Fight
Back,
NAT.
REV.
(Mar.
18,
2021,
6:30
AM),
https://www.nationalreview.com/2021/03/free-speech-is-under-threat-on-college-
campuses-heres-how-to-fight-back/.
81.
See
generally
Ellen
Schrecker,
Academic
Freedom
and
the
Cold
War,
38
ANTIOCH
REV.
313,
318-22
(1980).
82.
See,
e.g.,
Sweezy
v.
New
Hampshire,
354
U.S.
234,
236-38
(1957)
(plurality
opinion).
"We
believe
that
there
unquestionably
was
an
invasion
of
petitioner's
liberties
in
the
areas
of
academic
freedom
and
political
expression-
areas
in
which
government
should
be
extremely
reticent
to
tread."
Id.
at
250
(opinion
of
Warren,
C.J.).
477
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
The
original
impetus
for
the
anti-subversive
push
predated
the
Cold
War.
The
Bolshevik
Revolution
in
Russia
and
World
War
I
generated
their
own
demands
for
ensuring
that
subversive
ideas
did
not
get
a
foothold
in
the
United
States.
83
New
York
took
the
lead,
with
a
particular
focus
on
rooting subversives
out
of
public
schools.
8
4
The
laws
were
not
without
controversy.
Democratic
Governor
Alfred
E.
Smith
denounced
one
such
bill,
saying,
"It
deprives
teachers
of
their
right
to
freedom
of
thought,
it
limits
the
teaching
staff
of
the
public
schools to
those
only
who
lack
the
courage
of
mind
to
exercise
their
legal
right
to
just
criticism
of
existing
institutions."
85
Of
another
that
sought
to
create
a
licensing
system
for
private
schools,
he
wrote,
"[I]t
strikes
at
the
very
foundation
of
one
of
the
most
cardinal
institutions
of
our
nation-the
fundamental
right
of
the
people
to
enjoy
full
liberty
in
the
domain
of
idea
and
speech."
86
"It
is,"
he
thought,
"unthinkable
that
in
a
representative
democracy
there
should
be
delegated
to
any
body
of
men
the
absolute
power
to
prohibit
the
teaching
of
any
subject
of
which
it
may
disapprove."
87
Nonetheless,
just
a
few
years
later
the
American
Civil
Liberties
Union
reported
that
"[m]ore
laws
interfering
with
the
school
curriculum
have
been
passed
[since
World
War
I]
than
in
all
the
years
preceding."
88
While
the
current
anti-CRT
bills
have
taken
direct
aim
at
university
instruction,
the
anti-subversive
efforts
of
the
Cold
War
period
were
generally
less
direct. Loyalty
oaths
became
a
condition
for
employment
not
only
for
teachers
but
for
state
employees
of
all
sorts,
including
professors
at
state
universities.
89
New
York
eventually
barred
individuals
"from
any
office
or
position
in
the
service
of
the
state"
including
"in
a
state
normal
school
or
college,
or
any
other
state
educational
institution"
who
"willfully
and
deliberately
advocates,
advises
or
teaches
the
doctrine
that
the
government
of
the
United
States
.
. .
should
be
overthrown
or
overturned
by
force,
violence or
any unlawful
means"
or becomes
"a
member
of
any
society
or
group
of
persons
which
teaches
or
83.
PAUL
L.
MURPHY,
WORLD
WAR
I
AND
THE
ORIGIN
OF
CIVIL
LIBERTIES
IN
THE
UNITED
STATES
133-34,
177-78
(1979).
On
the
transition
in
free
speech
doctrine,
see
MARK
A.
GRABER,
TRANSFORMING
FREE
SPEECH
165-84
(1991);
DAVID
M.
RABBAN,
FREE
SPEECH
IN
ITS
FORGOTTEN
YEARS
175-76
(1997).
84.
See
generally
LAWRENCE
H.
CHAMBERLAIN,
LOYALTY
AND
LEGISLATIVE
ACTION
(1951).
85.
ALFRED
E.
SMITH,
2 PUBLIC
PAPERS
OF
ALFRED
E.
SMITH,
GOVERNOR
369
(1921).
86.
Id.
87.
Id.
at
370.
88.
AM.
C.L.
UNION,
THE
GAG
ON
TEACHING
4
(1931).
See
also,
M.J.
HEALE,
MCCARTHY'S
AMERICANS:
RED
SCARE
POLITICS
IN
STATE
AND
NATION,
1935-1965,
30-33
(1998)
("By
1953
the
great
majority
of
states
were
using
loyalty
oaths
of
some
kind.").
89.
HEALE,
supra
note
88,
at
30-31.
478
[Vol.
58
2023]
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
479
advocates"
such
a
doctrine.
9
0
The
notorious
Feinberg
Law
directed
the
state's
board
of
regents
to
adopt
rules
to
identify
and
remove
such
teachers
and
create
a
list
of
prohibited
subversive
organizations.
91
As
a
New
York
court
said
in
upholding
the
law,
"We
are
not
so
naive
as
to
accept
as
gospel
the
argument
that
a
teacher
who
believes
in
the
destruction
of
our
form
of
Government
will
not
affect
his
students."
92
The
state
had
a
particular
interest
in
the
thoughts
of
those
who
would
be
molding
"the
childish
mind."
93
The
fate
of
young
schoolchildren
might
have
been
of
particular
interest
to
legislators
in
the
postwar
period,
but
the
intellectual
environment
of
college
students
did
not
escape
their
attention.
94
University
professors
were
widely
required
to
attest
that
they
had
not
belonged
to
subversive
organizations
like
the
Communist
Party.
95
Texas
went
so
far
as
to
require
that
authors
of
school
textbooks
attest
that
they
had
not
been
a
member
of
a
movement
that
had
been
"designated
as
totalitarian,
fascist,
communist
or
subversive"
or
that
advocated
"acts
of
force
or
violence
to
deny
others
their
rights"
or
sought
to
"alter
the
form
of
Government
of
the
United
States
by
unconstitutional
means."
96
Refusing
to
testify
in
an
un-American
affairs
investigation
was
specified
as
grounds
for
dismissal
from
a
faculty
position.
97
State-university
officials,
like
the
president
of
Ohio
90.
N.Y.
Laws
1939,
c.
547,
as
amended
N.Y.
Laws
1940,
c.
564.
See
Adler
v.
Bd.
of
Educ.,
342
U.S.
485,
486
n.1
(1952)
(citing
the
statute).
91.
N.Y.
Laws
1949,
c.
360.
See
Adler,
342
U.S.
at
487
n.2
(citing
statute).
92.
L'Hommedieu
v.
Bd.
of
Regents,
95
N.Y.S.2d
443,
453
(N.Y.
App.
Div.
1950).
93.
Id.
94.
The
appointment
of
famed
British
philosopher
Bertrand
Russell
to
a
position
at
City
College
was
overturned
by
a
state
court
as
appalling
and
unlawful
in
part
because
the
taxpayers
of
New
York
"are
not
spending
that
money
nor
was
the
money
appropriated
for
the
purpose
of
employing
teachers
who
are
not
of
good
moral
character,"
and
"Mr.
Russell
has
taught
in
his
books
immoral
and
salacious
doctrines"
relating
to
premarital
sex.
Kay
v.
Bd.
of
Higher
Educ.,
18
N.Y.S.2d
821,
826-27
(N.Y.
Civ.
Ct.
1940).
95.
See
generally
ELLEN
W.
SCHRECKER,
No
IVORY
TOWER
(1986);
see
also
JANE
SANDERS,
COLD
WAR
ON
THE
CAMPUS
153-54
(1979).
96.
H.B.
21,
53d
Leg.,
Reg.
Sess.
(1953)
(requiring
an
oath
or
affirmation
of
Texas
educators).
The
state
attorney
general
instructed
the
board
of
education
that
the
provision
was
unconstitutional
and
should
not
be
implemented.
Att'y
Gen.
of
Tex.,
Opinion
No.
M-417
on
Whether
the
State
Board
of
Education
May
Require
a
Loyalty
Oath
(June
11,
1969).
The
state's
requirement
that
professors
sign
a
loyalty
oath
as
a
condition
of
employment
had
recently
been
struck
down
in
federal
court.
Gilmore
v.
James,
274
F.
Supp.
75,
79-80,
92-93
(N.D.
Tex.
1967),
affirmed
sub
nom.
James
v.
Gilmore,
389
U.S.
572
(1968)
(per
curiam).
"While
such
membership
may
furnish
a
basis
for
further
inquiry
into
an
applicant's
present
or
past
activities,
it
does
not
itself
constitute
a
threat
to
the
state."
Gilmore,
274
F.
Supp.
at
92.
97.
MARJORIE
HEINS,
PRIESTS
OF
OUR
DEMOCRACY
130-150
(2013).
New
York's
Section
903
was
struck
down
in
Slochower
v.
Bd.
of
Higher
Educ.,
350
U.S.
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
State
University,
declared
that
refusal
to
cooperate
with
anti-
Communism
investigations
was
"gross
insubordination"
and
"conduct
clearly
inimical
to
the
best
interests
of
the
university,"
which
created
"serious
doubt
as
to
[a
professor's]
fitness
for
the
position"
and
justified
the
stripping
of
tenure
and
termination
of
employment.
98
A
New
York
court
concluded
that
"the
assertion
of
the
privilege
against
self-incrimination
is
equivalent
to
a
resignation."
99
States
like
Arkansas
required
professors
to
divulge
the
organizations
with
which
they
had
been
associated.
1
00
States
like
North
Carolina
banned
speakers
who
had
advocated
the
overthrow
of
the
American
government
from
college
campuses.
101
The
fear
of
tenured
radicals
was
not
limited
to
state
universities
by
any
means.
When
Dwight
Eisenhower
left Columbia
University
to
move
to
the
White
House
after
a
brief
stint
as
its
president,
he
delivered
a
farewell
address
to
a
crowd
of
faculty
and
students.
He
confessed
that
before
arriving
at
Columbia
he
"heard
of
this
constant
rumor
and
black
suspicion
that
our
universities
were
cut
and
honeycombed
with
subversion."
102
He
agreed
to
accept
that
job
only
if
the
university
would
rid
itself
of
anyone
adhering
to
"any
kind
of
traitorous
doctrine."
103
In
"a
war
of
great
ideologies,"
"no
man
flying
a
war
plane
.
.
.
can
possibly
be more
important
than
the
teacher."
104
Fortunately,
in
his
short
stay
he
had
not
found
a
Communist
"behind
every
brick
on
the
campus,"
but
he
expected
the
campus
to
remain
vigilant
after
he
had
left.
105
As
pressure
built
on
universities
to
dispel
this
"black
suspicion,"
Yale
University
president
Charles
Seymour
551
(1956).
"We
do
not
decide
whether
a
claim
under
the
'privileges
or
immunities'
clause
was
raised
below,
since
we
conclude
the
summary
dismissal
of
[the]
appellant
in
the
circumstances
of
this
case
violates
due
process
of
law."
Id.
at
555
(citing
U.S.
CONST.
amend.
XIV,
§
1).
98.
Investigation
of
Communist
Activities
in
the
Los
Angeles
Area-Part
2:
Hearings
Before
the
Comm.
on
Un-American
Activities,
83d
Cong.
520
(1953).
See
also
ERVING
E.
BEAUREGARD,
HISTORY
OF
ACADEMIC
FREEDOM
IN
OHIO
93
(1988).
99.
Daniman
v.
Bd.
of
Educ.,
119
N.E.2d
373,
377
(N.Y.
1954).
100.
JEFF
WOODs,
BLACK
STRUGGLE,
RED
SCARE
70-77
(2004).
Arkansas's
Act
10
was
struck
down
in Shelton
v.
Tucker,
364
U.S.
479
(1960).
"The
statute's
comprehensive
interference
with
associational
freedom
goes
far
beyond
what
might
be
justified
in
the
exercise
of
the
State's
legitimate
inquiry
into
the
fitness
and
competency
of
its
teachers."
Id.
at
490
(reversing
the
judgments
below).
101.
WILLIAM
J.
BILLINGSLEY,
COMMUNISTS
ON
CAMPUS
1-21
(1999).
North
Carolina's
speaker
ban
was
struck
down
in
Dickson
v.
Sitterson,
280
F.
Supp.
486
(M.D.N.C.
1968).
See
id.
at
499
("When
the
statutes
and
regulations
in
question
are
applied
to
the
unbroken
line
of
Supreme
Court
decisions
.
. .
the
conclusion
is
inescapable
that
they
run
afoul
of
constitutional
principles.").
102.
William
R.
Conklin,
Eisenhower
Says
Farewell
to
Columbia
University,
N.Y.
TIMES,
Jan.
17,
1953,
at
Al.
103.
Id.
104.
Id.
105.
Id.
480
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
declared,
"There
will
be
no
witch-hunts
at
Yale
because
there
will
be
no
witches.
We
do
not
intend
to
hire
Communists."
10
6
The
American
Association
of
Universities
tried
to
walk
a
fine
line
in
a
1953
statement.
On
the
one
hand,
it
insisted
that
"the
scholar's
mission
requires
the
study
and
examination
of
unpopular
ideas,
of
ideas
considered
abhorrent
and
even
dangerous."1
07
The
scholar
"has
no
obligation
to
be
silent
in
the
face
of
popular
disapproval,"
and
the
teacher
has
the
responsibility
and
right
"to
express
his
own
critical
opinion
and
the
reasons
for
holding
it,"
limited
only
by
"the
requirements
of
citizenship,
of
professional
competence
and
good
taste."1
08
At
the
same
time,
those
appointed
to
a
university
faculty
have
"the
affirmative
obligation
of
being
diligent
and
loyal
in
citizenship"
and
a
particular
obligation
to
reject
the
Communist
Party
principles
including
"the
fomenting
of
world-wide
revolution
as
a
step
to
seizing
power;
the
use
of
falsehood
and
deceit
as
normal
means
of
persuasion;
[and]
thought
control-the
dictation
of
doctrines
which
must
be
accepted
and
taught
by
all
party
members."
09
Why
bother
targeting
hard-to-monitor
classroom
speech
when
it
was
possible
to
use
a
broader
brush
and
remove
instructors
for
their
extramural
expression
and
activity?
At
least
initially,
state
governments
understood
themselves
to
have
a
free
hand
to
purge
subversives
from
the
ranks
of
the
faculty
and
did
not
need
to
worry
over
what
those
subversives
were
actually
doing
in
the
classroom.
In
1952,
for
example,
the
Supreme
Court
upheld
the
Feinberg
Law
in
Adler
v.
Board
of
Education
of
the
City
of
New
York.110
Justice
Sherman
Minton
wrote
for
the
Court
that
"the
state
has
a
vital
concern"
with
those
employed
in
its
educational
institutions
and
has
the
right
to
"maintain
the
integrity
of
the
schools
as
a
part
of
ordered
society."
1
'
The
state
had
the
power
"to
protect
the
schools
from
pollution
and
thereby
to
defend
its
own
existence,"
and
individuals
106.
Quoted
in
SCHRECKER,
supra
note
95,
at
111.
While
Eisenhower
and
others
thought
that
in
the
midst
of
a
great
war
of
ideologies
universities
should
not
employ
the
enemies
of
freedom,
many
others
simply
concluded
that
Communists
were
different.
To
the
extent
that
the
"fundamental
doctrines
of
the
Communist
Party
deny
to
its
members
that
freedom
to
think
and
speak
independently
which
is
the
basis
of
University
policy,"
as
a
dean
at
the
University
of
Michigan
put
it,
committed
Communists
were
necessarily
unfit
to
be
scholars.
Id.
at
110.
107.
Ass'n
Am.
Univs.,
The
Rights
and
Responsibilities
of
Universities
and
their
Faculties,
1
UNiv.
BULL.
[Cal.]
161
(Mar.
24,
1953).
108.
Id.
at
162-63.
109.
Id.
at
167.
110.
342
U.S.
485
(1952).
111.
Id.
at
493
(1952).
Irving
Adler
was
a
public
high
school
math
teacher,
labor
union
leader,
and
a
longtime
member
of
the
Communist
Party.
He
had
declined
to
answer
the
required
question
about
his
organizational
affiliations.
Ralph
Blumenthal,
When
Suspicion
of
Teachers
Ran
Unchecked,
N.Y.
TIMES
(June
15,
2009),
https://www.nytimes.com/2009/06/16/nyregion/16teachers.html.
481
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
had
a
right
to
choose
between
their
freedom
to
advocate
radical
doctrines
and the
privilege
of
government
employment.
11 2
Minton's
view
would
soon
fall
out
of
favor
as
the
Court
confronted
the
application
of
anti-subversive
policies
in
higher
education
and
as
the
Court
became
more
civil
libertarian.
III.
THE
FIRST
AMENDMENT
AND
ACADEMIC
FREEDOM
Academic
freedom
in
the
United
States
was
first
and
primarily
a
matter
of
contract,
custom,
and
norms.
The
American
Association
of
University
Professors
("AAUP")
organized
in
the
early
twentieth
century
to
advocate
for
greater
recognition
of
and
protection
for
principles
of
academic
freedom
in
the
United
States.
11
3
Most
significantly,
the
AAUP
and
the
American
Association
of
Universities
agreed
to
a
joint
Statement
of
Principles
on
Academic
Freedom
and
Tenure
in
1940.114
The
1940
Statement
identified
three
basic
principles
of
academic
freedom
and
reduced
them
into
language
that
could
be,
and
was,
widely
adopted
as
university
policy
governing
employment
relations
with
faculty.
Specifically,
the
AAUP's
principles
of
academic
freedom
called
for
freedom
of
research,
freedom
of
teaching,
and
freedom
of
speech.
First,
professors
should
be free
to
conduct
and
publish
research
without
interference
or
censorship
from
their
university
employers.
11 5
Second,
professors
should
be
free
from
administrative
interference
with
classroom
discussions,
subject
to
the
condition
that
such
classroom
speech
should
be
germane
to
the
subject
matter
of
the
class
and
professionally
competent.
1
16
Third,
professors
should
be
free
to
"speak
or
write
as
citizens"
in
intramural
and
extramural
contexts
without
fear
of
institutional
reprisal.
11 7
Tenure
provides
procedural
protections
to
help
effectuate
those
principles
by
making
it
difficult
for
universities
to
terminate
faculty
without
cause.
118
It
was
only
after
the
articulation
and
general
acceptance
of
those
doctrines
that
the
Supreme
Court
began
to
suggest
their
relevance
to
American
constitutional
law.
The
Cold
War
put the
strength
of
the
commitment
of
American
higher
education
to
academic-freedom
112.
Adler,
342
U.S.
at
493.
113.
See
MATTHEW
W.
FINKIN
& ROBERT
C.
POST,
FOR
THE COMMON
GOOD
29-
52
(2009);
HENRY
REICHMAN,
UNDERSTANDING
ACADEMIC
FREEDOM
20-25
(2021).
114.
AM.
Ass'N
OF
UNIv.
PROFESSORS,
STATEMENT
OF
PRINCIPLES
ON
ACADEMIC
FREEDOM
AND
TENURE
(1940)
[hereinafter
STATEMENT
OF
PRINCIPLES],
https://www.aaup.org/file/1940%2oStatement.pdf.
115.
Id.
at
14;
FINKIN
&
POST,
supra
note
113,
at
53-78;
REICHMAN,
supra
note
113,
at
26-53.
116.
STATEMENT
OF
PRINCIPLES,
supra
note
114,
at
14;
FINKIN
&
PosT,
supra
note
113,
at
79-112;
REICHMAN,
supra
note
113,
at
54-82.
117.
STATEMENT
OF
PRINCIPLES,
supra
note
114,
at
14;
FINKIN
&
POST,
supra
note
113,
at
127-48;
REICHMAN,
supra
note
113,
at
83-114.
118.
STATEMENT
OF
PRINCIPLES,
supra
note
114,
at
15.
482
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
principles
to
the
test.
By
the
postwar
period,
American
universities
had
largely
adopted
the
position
that
tenure-line
faculty
could
not
be
treated
as
at-will
employees
and
dismissed
whenever
they
became
politically
inconvenient,
as
they
had
been
at
the
beginning
of
the
twentieth
century.
11
9
Those
academic-freedom
principles
were
not
simply
rolled
back
in
the
context
of
the
Cold
War,
but
there
was
substantial
pressure
to
find
a
way
of
accommodating
them
to
the
needs
of
the
anti-subversive
drive.
120
Under
myriad
circumstances,
expressing
subversive
ideas
could
be
characterized
as
a
sufficient
cause
to
merit
removal.1
21
The
emerging
system
of
contracts
and
custom
was
overridden
by
statute
and
administrative
activism.
At
least
in
the
context
of
state
universities,
the
Court
began
to
bolster
contracts
and
custom
with
the
First
Amendment.
A
precondition
for
that
specific
development
was
the
more
general
flowering
of
First
Amendment
doctrine
in
the
early
twentieth
century.
122
By
the
time
of
the
Cold
War,
the
Court
had
already
made
it
clear
that
radical
political
ideas
were
not
in
and
of
themselves
beyond
the
protection
of
the
First
Amendment.
12
3
In
doing
so
they
had
also
refrained
the
ethos
of
the
First
Amendment
itself.
Justice
Oliver
Wendell
Holmes
did
more
than
try
to
expand
the
margins
of
free
speech
protections
when
he
argued
that
[T]he
best
test
of
truth
is
the
power
of
the
thought
to
get
itself
accepted
in
the
competition
of
the
market,
and
that
truth
is
the
only
ground
upon
which
their
wishes
safely
can
be
carried
out.
That
at
any
rate
is
the
theory
of
our
Constitution.
It
is
an
experiment,
as
all
life
is
an
experiment.
Every
year
if
not
every
day
we
have
to
wager
our
salvation
upon
some
prophecy
based
upon
imperfect
knowledge.
While
that
experiment
is
part
of
our
system,
I
think
that
we
should
be
eternally
vigilant
against
attempts
to
check
the
expression
of
opinions
that
we
loathe
and
believe
to
be
fraught
with
death,
unless
they
so
imminently
threaten
immediate
interference
with
the
lawful
and
pressing
purposes
of
the
law
that
an
immediate
check
is
required
to
save
the
country.
1
24
Holmes
posited
a
new
"theory
of
our
Constitution"
that
was
grounded
in
making
space
for
"opinions
that
we
loathe"
and
119.
Robert
P.
Ludlum,
Academic
Freedom
and
Tenure:
A
History,
10
ANTIOCH
REV.
3,
13-14,
18
(1950);
MATTHEW
J.
HERTZOG,
PROTEcTIONS
OF
TENURE
AND
ACADEMIC
FREEDOM
IN
THE
UNITED
STATES
23-82
(2017).
120.
Schrecker,
supra
note
81,
at
15-20.
121.
Id.
at
15-20,
25-26.
122.
See
generally
William
W.
Van
Alstyne,
Academic
Freedom
and
the
First
Amendment
in
the
Supreme
Court
of
the
United
States:
An
Unhurried
Historical
Review,
53
LAW
&
CONTEMP.
PROBS.
79
(1990).
123.
See
Herndon
v.
Lowery,
301
U.S.
242,
259-261
(1937).
124.
Abrams
v.
United
States,
250
U.S.
616,
630
(1919)
(Holmes,
J.,
dissenting).
483
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
countering
ideas
only
with
argument
and
persuasion.
125
Similarly,
as
he
put
it
a
few
years
later,
"If
in
the
long
run
the
beliefs
expressed
in
proletarian
dictatorship
are
destined
to
be
accepted
by
the
dominant
forces
of
the
community,
the
only
meaning
of
free
speech
is
that
they
should
be
given
their
chance
and
have
their
way."
12
6
Or,
"if
there
is
any
principle
of
the
Constitution
that
more
imperatively
calls
for
attachment
than
any other,
it
is
the
principle
of
free
thought-not
free
thought
for
those
who
agree
with
us
but
freedom
for
the
thought
that
we
hate."
127
For
this
new
vision
of
the
Constitution,
"it
cannot
show
lack
of
attachment
to
the
principles
of
the
Constitution
that
[a
citizen]
thinks
that
it
can
be
improved."
128
Justice
Louis
Brandeis
added,
"Those
who
won
our
independence
believed
that
the
final
end
of
the
State
was
to
make
men
free
to
develop
their
faculties,
and
that
in
its
government
the
deliberative
forces
should
prevail
over
the
arbitrary."
129
Such
views
initially
expressed
in
dissent
over
time
found
their
way
into
the
Court's
majority.130
The
vision
of
the
Constitution
advanced
by
Holmes
and
Brandeis
still
put
some
speech
outside
the
bounds
of
constitutional
protection;
however,
it
not
only
brought
far
more
speech
under
the
umbrella
of
the
First
Amendment
but
also
placed
the
contestation
over
ideas
at
the
heart
of
the
American
constitutional
project.
The
state
could
rule
out
violent
action,
but
it
could
not
rule
out
the
possibility
of
radical
political
change.
If
the
First
Amendment
enshrined
the
belief
that
the
ideas
we
hate
have
to
be
overcome
through
argument
rather
than
coercion,
then
it
was
a
repudiation
of
the
American
constitutional
experiment
for
the
state
to
attempt
to
suppress
disfavored
ideas.
The
very
"theory
of
our
Constitution"
is
that
ideas
we
think
are
true
must
be
put
through
the
crucible
of
criticism,
and
that
ideas
we
hate
must
be
allowed
to
have
their
say.
131
As
Justice
Frank
Murphy
emphasized
in
a
different
First
Amendment
setting,
"It
is
our
proud
achievement
to
have
demonstrated
that
unity
and
strength
are
best
accomplished,
not
by
enforced
orthodoxy
of
views,
but
by
diversity
of
opinion
through
the
fullest
possible
measure
of
freedom
of
conscience
and thought."
3 2
Justice
Robert
Jackson
kicked
an
important
leg
out
from
under
the
state's
authority
to
stifle
dissent
in
schools
in
the
flag
salute
case,
125.
Id.
126.
Gitlow
v.
New
York,
268
U.S.
652,
673
(1925)
(Holmes,
J.,
dissenting).
127.
United
States
v.
Schwimmer,
279
U.S.
644,
654-655
(1929)
(Holmes,
J.,
dissenting).
128.
Id.
at
654.
129.
Whitney
v.
California,
274
U.S.
357,
375
(1927)
(Brandeis,
J.,
concurring).
130.
Stromberg
v.
California,
283
U.S.
359,
369
(1931).
131.
Abrams
v.
United
States,
250
U.S.
616,
630
(1919)
(Holmes,
J.,
dissenting).
132.
Martin
v.
City
of
Struthers,
319
U.S.
141,
150
(1943)
(Murphy,
J.,
concurring).
484
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
declaring,
"If
there
is
any
fixed
star
in
our
constitutional
constellation,
it
is
that
no
official,
high
or
petty,
can
prescribe
what
shall
be
orthodox
in
politics,
nationalism,
religion,
or
other
matters
of
opinion
or
force
citizens
to
confess
by
word
or
act
their
faith
therein."
13 3
The
very
"purpose
of
the
First
Amendment"
is
to
protect
"from
all
official
control"
"the
sphere
of
intellect
and
spirit."
13
4
The
"principle
of
free
thought"
is
at
the
center
of
the
highest
of
constitutional
ideals.
13
5
The
tolerance
of
free
speech
did
not
just
set
outer
bounds
on
the
imperative
of
maintaining
public
order.
Protecting
free
speech
was
the
constitutional
imperative
itself.
If
freedom
of
thought
is
a
core
constitutional
value,
then
impinging
on
academic
freedom
could
readily
be
seen
as
a
betrayal
of
the
constitutional
enterprise.
Across
the
1950s
and
into
the
1960s,
the
Court
began
to
give
constitutional
recognition
to
principles
of
academic
freedom.
When
Minton
wrote
for
the
Court
upholding
the
Feinberg
Law,
former
Yale
Law
professor
Justice
William
O.
Douglas
wrote
a
dissent
giving
academic
freedom
a
toehold
in
the
First
Amendment.
136
He
began
necessarily
with
the
problem
of
government-employee
speech.
Minton
relied
on
the
traditional
assumption
famously
captured
in
an
early
Holmesian
quip,
"The
petitioner
may
have
a
constitutional
right
to
talk
politics,
but
he
has
no
constitutional
right
to
be
a
policeman."
137
Douglas,
joined
by
Justice
Hugo
Black,
by
contrast
could
not
"find
in
our
constitutional
scheme
the
power
of
a
state
to
place
its
employees
in
the
category
of
second-class
citizens
by
denying
them
freedom
of
thought
and
expression."
1
3
8
Douglas
quickly
turned
his
attention
to
the
implications
of
anti-
subversive
measures
operating
in
schools
and
emphasized
how
they
would
necessarily
encroach
on
the
intellectual
freedom
that
schools
should
be
fostering.
The
intrinsic
problem
of
"guilt
by
association"
raised
by
the
requirement
of
identifying
current
and
past
membership
in
potentially
subversive
groups
"is
certain
to
raise
havoc
with
academic
freedom."
13
9
Fearing
being
enmeshed
in
such
investigations
"when
the
witch
hunt
is
on,"
those
subjected
to
such
requirements
"will
tend
to
shrink
from
any
association
that
stirs
controversy"
and
as
a
result
"freedom
of
expression
will
be
stifled."
140
More
directly,
"the
law
inevitably
turns
the
school
system
into
a
spying
project."141
With
students
and
parents
becoming
"informers,"
133.
W.
Va.
State
Bd.
of
Educ.
v.
Barnette,
319
U.S.
624,
642
(1943).
134.
Id.
135.
United
States
v.
Schwimmer,
279
U.S.
644,
655
(1929).
136.
Adler
v.
Bd.
of
Educ.,
342
U.S.
485,
508
(1952)
(Douglas,
J.,
dissenting).
137.
McAuliffe
v.
City
of
New
Bedford,
29
N.E.
517,
517
(1892).
138.
Adler,
342
U.S.
at
508
(Douglas,
J.,
dissenting).
139.
Id.
at
508-09.
140.
Id.
at
509.
141.
Id.
485
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
"it
is
a
system
which
searches
for
hidden
meanings
in
a
teacher's
utterances."
14 2
Where
"teachers
are
under
constant
surveillance,"
"[t]here
can
be
no
real
academic
freedom."
1
4
3
Where
every
utterance
could
become
grounds
for
political
reprisal,
"[s]upineness
and
dogmatism
take
the
place
of
inquiry."
1
44
Such
laws
force
teachers
into
mouthing
"the
orthodox
view,"
"the
conventional
thought,"
and
to
avoid
any
"adventurous
thinking."
1
4
5
"A
deadening
dogma
takes
the
place
of
free
inquiry."
146
Justice
Hugo
Black
wrote
separately
without
using
the
term
"academic
freedom,"
but
similarly
emphasized
that
"these
laws
rest
on
the
belief
that
government
should
supervise
and
limit
the
flow
of
ideas
into
the
minds
of
men."
147
The
First
Amendment
was
designed
to
prevent
"a
transient
majority"
from
being
able "to
select
the
ideas
people
can
think
about."
148
The
Court's
majority
reached
a
different
conclusion
than
it
had
in
Adler
when
confronted
with
an
Oklahoma
statute
that
it
thought
swept
more
broadly
than
the
Feinberg
Law.
Dismissing
government
employees
who
had
no
specific
knowledge
of
the
subversive
purposes
of
the
organizations
that
they
had
joined
"offends
due
process."
149
This
time
former
Harvard
law
professor
Justice
Felix
Frankfurter
wrote
separately
for
himself
and
Douglas
in
laying
out
specific
concerns
with
how
such laws
affected
teachers.
150
The
case
from
Oklahoma
involved
not
secondary
school
teachers
but
members
of
the
faculty
and
staff
at
the
Oklahoma
Agricultural
and
Mechanical
College
(now
Oklahoma
State
University).151
Frankfurter
did
not
use
the
specific
term
"academic
freedom,"
but
he
thought
"in
view
of
the
nature
of
the
teacher's
relation
to
the
effective
exercise
of
the
rights
which
are
safeguarded
by
the
Bill
of
Rights
and
by
the
Fourteenth
Amendment,
inhibition
of
freedom
of
thought,
and
of
action
upon
thought,
in
the
case
of
teachers
brings
the
safeguards
of
those
amendments
vividly
into
operation."
15 2
Teachers
were,
Frankfurter
warned,
"the
priests
of
our
democracy"
who
"must
be
exemplars
of
open-mindedness
and
free
inquiry."
1
53
They
"must
be
free
to
sift
evanescent
doctrine,
qualified
by
time
and
circumstance,
from
that
restless,
enduring
process
of
extending
the
bounds
of
understanding
142.
Id.
at
510.
143.
Id.
144.
Id.
145.
Id.
146.
Id.
147.
Id.
at
497 (Black,
J.,
dissenting).
148.
Id.
149.
Wieman
v.
Updegraff,
344
U.S.
183,
191
(1952).
150.
Frankfurter
had
dissented
in
Adler,
but
there
he
had
thought
the
case
was
not
yet
ripe
for
a
constitutional
argument.
Adler,
342
U.S.
at
497-98
(Frankfurter,
J., dissenting).
151.
Wieman,
344
U.S.
at
185.
152.
Id.
at
195
(Frankfurter,
J.,
concurring).
153.
Id.
at
196.
486
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
and
wisdom."
15
4
He
concluded
with
an
extended
quote
from
Robert
Hutchins,
the
former
dean
of
Yale
Law
School
and
influential
president
of
the
University
of
Chicago,
that
began,
[A]
university
is
a
place
that
is
established
and
will
function
for
the
benefit
of
society,
provided
it
is
a
center
of
independent
thought.
It
is
a
center
of
independent
thought
and
criticism
that
is
created
in
the
interest
of
the
progress
of
society,
and
the
one
reason
that
we
know
that
every
totalitarian
government
must
fail
is
that
no
totalitarian
government
is
prepared
to
face
the
consequences
of
creating
free
universities.
155
The
quote
was
drawn
from
testimony
that
Hutchins
had
recently
given
before
a
House
committee
investigating
tax-exempt
foundations,
where
he
was
grilled
in
part
about
allegations
of
subversive
activities
at
the
University
of
Chicago.
15
6
Hutchins
contended
that
the
Communists
were
best
met
by
Americans
maintaining
and
developing
"the
basic
sources
of
our
strength,"
namely
"the
western
tradition
of
freedom,
freedom
of
thought,
freedom
of
discussion,
and
freedom
of
association."
157
As
a
university
president,
Hutchins
thought
he
had
an
obligation
to
take
"immediate
action"
if
any
member
of
the
faculty
"had
been
engaged
in
subversive
activity,"
but
mere
membership
in
questionable
organizations
or
interest
in
"the
study
of
Marxism"
did
not
disqualify
someone
from
being
a
member
in
good
standing
of
the
scholarly
community.
1
58
The
Court
soon
had
another
opportunity
to
consider
the
impact
of
anti-subversive
measures
on
the
academic
activities
of
universities.
The
attorney
general
of
New
Hampshire
launched
an
investigation
of
Paul
Sweezy,
a
Marxist
economist
who
had
left
a
lecturer
position
at
Harvard
University
to
found
the
socialist
journal
Monthly
Review.
15
9
In
1954,
Sweezy
gave
a
guest
lecture
in
an
undergraduate
class
at
the
University
of
New
Hampshire.
160
Sweezy
refused
to
answer
questions
about
the
lecture
as
he
had
refused
to
answer
questions
about
his
other
activities
and
was
held
in
contempt.1
61
Writing
for
the
Court,
Chief
Justice
Earl
Warren
observed,
"We
believe
that
there
unquestionably
was
an
invasion
of
petitioner's
liberties
in
the
areas
of
academic
freedom
and
free
expression-areas
in
which
the
154.
Id.
155.
Id.
at
197.
156.
Tax-Exempt
Foundations:
Hearings
Before
the
Select
Comm.
to
Investigate
Tax-Exempt
Foundations
&
Comparable
Organizations,
82d
Cong.
291
(1952).
157.
Id.
158.
Id.
at
292-93.
159.
Sweezy
v.
New
Hampshire,
354
U.S.
234,
258
(1957)
(Frankfurter,
J.,
concurring).
160.
Id.
at
243
(majority
opinion).
161.
Id.
at
259
(Frankfurter,
J.,
concurring).
487
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
government
should
be
extremely
reticent
to
tread."
1
62
He
then
elaborated,
The
essentiality
of
freedom
in
the
community
of
American
universities
is
almost
self-evident.
No
one
should
underestimate
the
vital
role
in
a
democracy
that
is
played
by
those
who
guide
and
train
our
youth.
To
impose
any
strait
jacket
upon
the
intellectual
leaders
in
our
colleges
and
universities
would
imperil
the
future
of
our
Nation.
No
field
of
education
is
so
thoroughly
comprehended
by
man
that
new
discoveries
cannot
yet
be
made.
Particularly
is
that
true
in
the
social
sciences,
where
few,
if
any,
principles
are
accepted
as
absolutes.
Scholarship
cannot
flourish
in
an
atmosphere
of
suspicion
and
distrust.
Teachers
and
students
must
always
remain
free
to
inquire,
to
study
and
to
evaluate,
to
gain
new
maturity
and
understanding;
otherwise,
our
civilization
will
stagnate
and
die.
163
The
state
supreme
court
had
admitted
as
much
but
thought
the
state's
interest
justified
the
imposition
on
Sweezy's
liberty.1
64
The
Warren
Court
disagreed,
"We
do
not
now
conceive
of
any
circumstance
wherein
a
state
interest
would
justify
infringement
of
rights
in
these
fields."
1
65
But
the
Court
ultimately
chose
instead
to
reverse
the
state
courts
on
the
inadequacy
of
the
legislature's
authorization
of
such
an
intrusive
investigation.1
6
6
Frankfurter,
joined
by
Justice
John
Marshall
Harlan,
thought
the
majority's
alternative
grounds
were
in fact
more
intrusive
to
state
authority.
167
Frankfurter
preferred
instead
to
rest
the
case
solely
on
the
academic-freedom
question.
The
state's
justification
was
inadequate
to
overcome
the
"grave
harm
resulting
from
governmental
intrusion
into
the intellectual
life
of
a
university."16
8
The
intellectual
life
of
a
university
"must
be
left
as
unfettered
as
possible"
and
intrusions
upon
it
could
be
justified
only
"for
reasons
that
are
exigent
and
obviously
compelling."
169
Frankfurter
thought
obvious
162.
Id.
at
250
(majority
opinion).
163.
Id.
164.
Id.
at
249-50.
165.
Id.
at
251.
166.
Id.
("But
we
do
not
need
to
reach
such
fundamental
questions
of
state
power
to
decide
this
case
....
There
was
nothing
to
connect
the
questioning
of
petitioner
with
this
fundamental
interest
of
the
State.").
This
was
not
an
uncommon
strategy
for
the
Warren
Court.
See
KEITH
E.
WHITTINGTON,
REPUGNANT
LAws
221
(2019).
167.
Sweezy,
354
U.S.
at
257
(Frankfurter,
J.,
concurring)
("[W]hether
the
Attorney
General
of
New
Hampshire
acted
within
the
scope
of
the
authority
given
him
by
the
state
legislature
is
a
matter
for
the
decision
of
the
courts
of
that
State.").
168.
Id.
at
261.
169.
Id.
at
262.
488
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
the
dependence
of
a
free
society
on
free
universities.
This
means
the
exclusion
of
governmental
intervention
in
the
intellectual
life
of
a
university.
It
matters
little
whether
such
intervention
occurs
avowedly
or
through
action
that
inevitably
tends
to
check
the
ardor
and
fearlessness
of
scholars,
qualities
at
once
so
fragile
and
so
indispensable
for
fruitful
academic
labor.
170
Frankfurter
again
concluded
with
a
lengthy
quote,
in
this
case
from
a
statement
on
open
universities
in
South
Africa:
It
is
the
business
of
a
university
to
provide
that
atmosphere
which
is
most
conducive
to
speculation,
experiment
and
creation.
It
is
an
atmosphere
in
which
there
prevail
'the
four
essential
freedoms'
of
a
university-to
determine
for
itself
on
academic
grounds
who
may
teach,
what
may
be
taught,
how
it
shall
be
taught,
and
who
may
be
admitted
to
study.
171
In
Shelton
v.
Tucker,1
7
2
the
Court
struck
down
an
Arkansas
statute
that
required
teachers
at
public
educational
institutions,
including
universities,
to
file
an
annual
affidavit
listing
all
of
their
organizational
affiliations.
17
3
When
the
Arkansas
legislature
adopted
Act
10
in
1958,
the
NAACP
was
as
much
a
concern
as
the
Communist
Party.
1
74
The
Court
recognized
(as
it
had
in
Adler)
that
the
state
had
the
right
"to
investigate
the
competence
and
fitness
of
those
whom
it
hires
to
teach
in
its
schools,"
1
75
but
also
noted
(as
it
had
in
Sweezy)
that
"[t]he
vigilant
protection
of
constitutional
freedoms
is
nowhere
more
vital
than
in
the
community
of
American
schools."
176
Ultimately,
the
majority
thought
the
state's
inquiry
was
too
sweeping
and
indiscriminate.
17 7
Notably,
Frankfurter
now
found
himself
in
dissent.
Although
heedful
of
the
danger
of
"crude
intrusions
by
the
state
into
the
atmosphere
of
creative
freedom
in
which
alone
the
spirit
and
mind
of
a
teacher
can
fruitfully
function,"
he
thought
that
academic
freedom
"in
its
most
creative
reaches,
is
dependent
in
no
small
part
upon
the
careful
and
discriminating
selection
of
teachers."1
78
He
did
not
think
the
record
had
yet
established
that
the
170.
Id.
171.
Id.
at
263.
(Frankfurter,
J.,
concurring)
(quoting
CoNF.
OF
REPRESENTATIVES
OF
THE
UNIV.
OF
CAPE
TOWN
&
THE
UNIV.
OF
THE
WITWATERSRAND,
THE
OPEN
UNIVERSITIES
IN
SOUTH
AFRICA
11-12
(1957)).
The
statement
was
the
product
of
a
conference
organized
to
protest
the
imposition
of
racial
apartheid
to
the
heretofore
color-blind
universities.
172.
364
U.S.
479
(1960).
173.
Id.
at
480,
490.
174.
JoY
ANN-WILLIAMSON-LoTT,
JIM
CROW
CAMPUS:
HIGHER
EDUCATION
AND
THE
STRUGGLE
FOR
A
NEW
SOUTHERN
SOCIAL
ORDER
60-68
(2018);
WOODS,
supra
note
100,
at
70-77.
175.
Shelton,
364
U.S.
at
485.
176.
Id.
at
487.
177.
Id.
at
490.
178.
Id.
at
490,
496.
489
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
state
was
using
Act
10
"to
further
a
scheme
of
terminating
the
employment
of
teachers
solely
because
of
their
membership
in
unpopular
organizations."1
7
9
As
long
as
the
state
was
just
asking
questions,
Frankfurter
was
not
prepared
to
intervene.
180
Near
the
end
of
the
Warren
Court,
the
justices
had
an
opportunity
to
revisit
the
Feinberg
Law
and
in
doing
so
consolidate
the
developments
in
the
Court's
thinking
since
Adler
had
been
decided
fifteen
years
before.
In
Keyishian
v.
Board
of
Regents,1
8
1
members
of
the
faculty
in
the
State
University
of
New York
system
had
refused
to
sign
certificates
saying
that
they
had
never
been
Communists.1
82
Writing
for
the
Court,
Justice
William
Brennan
observed
that
"pertinent
constitutional
doctrines
have
since
rejected
the
premises
upon
which
that
conclusion
[in
Adler]
rested."
18
3
The
Court
now
thought
the
law
was
fatally
vague
and
overbroad.
"The
crucial
consideration
is
that
no
teacher
can
know
just
where
the
line
is
drawn
between
'seditious' and
nonseditious
utterances
and
acts."
184
"Does
the
teacher
who
informs
his
class
about
the
precepts
of
Marxism
or
the
Declaration
of
Independence
violate
this
prohibition?"
185
"[D]oes
the
prohibition
of
distribution
of
matter
'containing'
the
doctrine
[of
the
forceful
overthrow
of
the
existing
government]
bar
histories
of
the
evolution
of
Marxist
doctrine
or
tracing
the
background
of
the
French,
American,
or
Russian
revolutions?"
186
The
inevitable
effect
of
the
law
was
to
interfere
with
constitutionally
protected
academic
freedom.
It
would
be
a
bold
teacher
who
would
not
stay
as
far
as
possible
from
utterances
or
acts
which
might
jeopardize
his
living
by
enmeshing
him
in
this
intricate
machinery.
The
uncertainty
as
to
the
utterances
and
acts
proscribed
increases
that
caution
in
"those
who
believe
the
written
law
means
what
it
says."
Baggett
v.
Bullitt,
377
U.S.
360,
374
(1964).
The
result
must
be
to
stifle
"that
free
play
of
the
spirit
which
all
teachers
ought
especially
to
cultivate
and
practice
.
. .
."
That
probability
is
enhanced
by
the
provisions
requiring
an
annual
review
of
every
teacher
to
determine
whether
any
utterance
or
act
of
his,
inside
the
classroom
or
out,
came
within
the
sanctions
of
the
laws.
187
179.
Id.
at
496.
180.
Frankfurter
was
understating
the
impact
that
Act
10
had
already
had
on
university
campuses
in
the
state.
See
WOODS,
supra
note
100,
at
75-78.
181.
385
U.S.
589 (1967).
182.
Id.
at
592.
183.
Id.
at
595.
184.
Id.
at
599.
185.
Id.
at
600.
186.
Id.
at
600-01.
187.
Id.
at
601-02.
490
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
Citing
the
cases
since
Adler,
Brennan
gave
firm
recognition
of
a
constitutionalized
academic
freedom.
Our
Nation
is
deeply
committed
to
safeguarding
academic
freedom,
which
is
of
transcendent
value
to
all
of
us,
and
not
merely
to
the
teachers
concerned.
That
freedom
is
therefore
a
special
concern
of
the
First
Amendment,
which
does
not
tolerate
laws
that
cast
a
pall
of
orthodoxy
over
the
classroom.
18
8
Laws
that
trench
on
that
freedom
must
be
drawn
with
a
"narrow
specificity"
that
the
anti-subversive
laws
lacked.
18
9
"The
danger
of
that
chilling
effect
upon
the
exercise
of
vital
First
Amendment
rights
must
be
guarded
against
by
sensitive
tools
which
clearly
inform
teachers
what
is
being
proscribed."
1
90
After
Keyishian,
a
First
Amendment
interest
in
an
individualized
academic
freedom
seemed
firmly
established,
if
not
entirely
clear
in
its
implications.
Academic
freedom
was
now
recognized
as
"a
special
concern
of
the
First
Amendment,"191
if
not
exactly
a
right
comparable
to
classic
First
Amendment
rules.
1
92
In
the
next
term,
the
Court
struck
down
an
anti-evolution
statute
with
Justice
Abe
Fortas
noting,
"It
is
much
too
late
to
argue
that
the
State
may
impose
upon
the
teachers
in
its
schools
any
conditions
that
it
chooses,
however
restrictive
they
may
be
of
constitutional
guarantees."
19
3
The
Cold
War
(and
eventually
in
the
South
the
Jim
Crow)
194
wave
of
anti-
subversive
measures
by
state
legislatures
had
forced
the
Court
to
confront
efforts
to
suppress
professorial
speech.
In
doing
so,
they
recognized
that
universities
are
what
Paul
Horwitz
has
called
"First
Amendment
institutions"
1
9 5
and
what
Jonathan
Rauch
has
called
"reality-based
communities"
196
because
of
their
central
role
in
generating,
investigating,
and
promulgating
ideas.
Suppressing
ideas
in
a
university
context
poses
a
particular
threat
to
the
values
that
the
First
Amendment
enshrines.
188.
Id.
at
603.
189.
Id.
at
604
(quoting
Brennan's
own
majority
opinion
in
NAACP
v.
Button,
371
U.S.
415,
433
(1963)).
190.
Keyishian,
385
U.S.
at
604.
191.
Id.
at
603.
192.
PosT,
supra
note
17,
at
112-14.
193.
Epperson
v.
Arkansas,
393
U.S.
97,
107
(1968)
(citing
Keyishian,
385
U.S.
at
605-06).
194.
A
year
after
the
Court
struck
down
Arkansas's
Act
10
in
Shelton,
the
historian
C.
Vann
Woodward
reported
that
"academic
freedom
is
still
taking
a
beating
in
the
lower
South."
C.
Vann
Woodward,
The
Unreported
Crisis
in
the
Southern
Colleges,
HARPER'S
MAG.,
Oct.
1,
1962,
at
82.
195.
PAUL
HORWITZ,
FIRST
AMENDMENT
INSTITUTIONS
(2013).
196.
JONATHAN
RAUCH,
THE
CONSTITUTION
OF
KNOWLEDGE:
A
DEFENSE
OF
TRUTH
100-02
(2021).
491
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
IV.
PICKERING,
GARCETTI,
AND
ACADEMIC
FREEDOM
University
professors
may
be
the
"priests
of
our
democracy"
with
which
the
First
Amendment
has
a
particular
concern,
but
when
they
work
at
state
universities,
they
are
still
government
employees.
197
The
Court
has
not
clearly
resolved
the
tension
inherent
in
that
framework.
As
government
employees,
professors
can
be
disciplined
or
penalized
for
their
conduct,
including
in
some
cases
for
their
speech
acts.
198
What
then
are
the
limits
to
when
university
officials
acting
as
agents
of
the
state
can
sanction
members
of
the
faculty
for
their
speech,
and
what
are
the
implications
for
the
anti-CRT
policies?
In
this
Part,
I
offer
an
approach
to
reconciling
constitutional
protections
for
academic
freedom
with
governmental
supervision
of
its
employees.
In
doing
so
I
extend
the
principles
that
the
Court
has
laid
out
regarding
the
First
Amendment
and
government-employee
speech
in
the
particular
context
of
a
university
setting.
The
Court
established
a
balancing
test
for
assessing
when
governmental
interests
can
override
the
First
Amendment
interests
of
a
government
employee
in
Pickering
v.
Board
of
Education.
199
Pointing
to
the
academic-freedom
cases
arising
out
of
the
McCarthy
era,
Pickering
recognized
that
government
employees
had
First
Amendment
rights
that
governments
as employers
had
to
respect
but
also
identified
circumstances
in
which
those
rights
could
nonetheless
be
overridden.
200
Pickering
arose
in
the
context
of
a
public-school
teacher
engaging
in
extramural
speech,
where
we
might
think
that
First
Amendment
interests
are
particularly
high.
Marvin
Pickering
had
written
a
letter
to
the
editor
that
was
published
in
a
local
newspaper
in
which
he
criticized
a
proposed
school
bond
issuance
that
was
supported
by
school
administrators
and
the
board
of
education.
20
1
He
was
fired
for
writing
the
letter.
202
As
the
Court
noted,
"The
problem
in
any
case
is
to
arrive
at
a
balance
between
the
interests
of
the
teacher,
as
a
citizen,
in
commenting
upon
matters
of
public
concern
and
the
interest
of
the
State,
as
an
employer,
in
promoting
the
efficiency
of
the
public
services
it
performs
through
its
197.
Wieman
v.
Updegraff,
344
U.S.
183,
196
(1952).
198.
Moreover,
professors
as
employees
are
routinely
evaluated
in
part
on
the
content,
or
quality,
of
their
professorial
speech.
199.
391
U.S.
563
(1968).
200.
Id.
at
568
("To
the
extent
that
the
Illinois
Supreme
Court's
opinion
may
be
read
to
suggest
that
teachers
may
constitutionally
be compelled
to
relinquish
the
First
Amendment
rights
they
would
otherwise
enjoy
as
citizens
to
comment
on
matters
of
public
interest
in
connection
with
the
operation
of
the
public
schools
in which
they
work,
it
proceeds
on
a
premise
that
has
been
unequivocally
rejected
in
numerous
prior
decisions
of
this
Court.").
201.
Id.
at
566.
202.
Id.
492
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
employees."
20
3
The
First
Amendment
rights
of
government
employees
are
not
only
not
absolute
but
necessarily
more
circumscribed
than
the
speech
of
a
private
citizen.
The
Pickering
Court
identified
both
the
circumstances
in
which
employee
speech
is
entitled
to
First
Amendment
protection
and
the
conditions
under
which
an
employee
can
be
sanctioned
for
such
speech.
Government-employee
speech
is
entitled
to
First
Amendment
consideration
when
the
employee,
"as
a
citizen,"
is
"commenting
upon
matters
of
public
concern."
20
4
Even
so,
the
government
employer
can
sanction
an
employee
for
such
speech
if,
in
this
case,
it
could
demonstrate
that
the
teacher's
speech
"impeded
the
teacher's
proper
performance
of
his
daily
duties
in
the
classroom"
2
05
or
"interfered
with
the
regular
operation
of
the
schools
generally."
2
06
The
government
must
have
an
interest
in
suppressing
the
employee's
speech
that
is
particular
to
the
employment
context
and
distinguishable
from
the
government's
general
interest
in
suppressing
such
speech
if
it
had
come
from
an ordinary
citizen.
207
Similarly
and
in
a
separate
case,
the
Court
concluded
that
a
professor
at
a
state
university
could
not
be
dismissed
specifically
because
he
had
provided
testimony
to
a
legislative
committee
that
was
critical
of
the
board
of
regents.
20
8
In
Connick
v.
Myers,
20
9
the
Court
further
elaborated
on
the
conditions
in
which
government-employee
speech
is
protected.
2
10
Connick
arose
in
the
context
of
a
district
attorney's
office
rather
than
a
school
and
internal
speech
within
the
office
about
office
policies.
21
1
There,
the
Court
emphasized
"the
common-sense
realization
that
government
offices
could
not
function
if
every
employment
decision
became
a
constitutional
matter."
2
12
The
employee's
constitutional
interest
is
at
its
highest
when
the
government
"s[eeks]
to
suppress
the
rights
of
public
employees
to
participate
in
public
affairs,"
as
it
had
done
in
the
anti-subversive
cases.
213
By
contrast,
"when
employee
expression
cannot
be
fairly
considered
as
relating
to
any
matter
of
political,
social,
or
other
concern
to
the
community,"
no
substantial
First
Amendment
interests
arise
that
might
hinder
a
governmental
employer
from
sanctioning
an
employee
for
such
speech.
21
4
When
an
employee
speaks
"upon
matters
only
of
personal
203.
Id.
at
568.
204.
Id.
at
568.
205.
Id.
at
572-73.
206.
Id.
at
573.
207.
Id.
208.
Perry
v.
Sindermann,
408
U.S.
593,
598
(1972).
209.
461
U.S.
138
(1983).
210.
Id.
at
138.
211.
Id.
at
141.
212.
Id.
at
143.
213.
Id.
at
144-45.
214.
Id.
at
146.
493
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
interest"
or
"internal
office
affairs,"
the
courts
should
not
intervene.
2
15
The
First
Amendment
does
not
"constitutionalize
the
employee
grievance."
2
1
6
The
"content,
form,
and
context
of
a
given
statement"
helps
determine
whether
it
"addresses
a
matter
of
public
concern."
217
The
Connick
Court
also
elaborated
on
the
government's
interest
in
addressing
"the disruption
of
the
office
and
the
destruction
of
working
relationships"
that
stem
from
an
employee's
speech,
but
warned
that
"a
stronger
showing
may
be
necessary
if
the
employee's
speech
more
substantially
involved
matters
of
public
concern."
218
The
Pickering
balancing
test
was
significantly
modified
in
Garcetti
v.
Ceballos,
219
which
has
particular
significance
to
the
context
of
the
anti-CRT
policies.
220
Like
Connick,
Garcetti
involved
internal
communications
in
a
district
attorney's
office.
2
21
The
key
issue
in
Garcetti
was
whether
those
internal
communications,
there
a
memo
regarding
the
disposition
of
a
case
being
handled
by
the
office,
passed
the
initial
threshold
of
the
Pickering
test
and
involved
speech
in
which
the
employee
had
a
First
Amendment
interest.
222
Unlike
Connick,
the
memo
in
Garcetti
did
not
deal
with
a
matter
of
only
"personal
interest"
but
rather
with
the
substantive
public
business
with
which
the
office
routinely
dealt.
223
Although
the
memo
in
question
addressed
matters
of
public
interest,
the
Court
concluded
that
the
deputy
district
attorney
was
not
speaking
"as
a
citizen"
in
writing
the
memo
to
his
superiors.
224
Unlike
Pickering's
letter
to
the
editor
or
the
speech
suppressed
in
the
anti-subversive
cases,
the
internal
office
memo
was
not
promoting
an
"informed,
vibrant
dialogue
in
a
democratic
society."
225
The
Garcetti
Court
accepted
that
some
"speech
within
the
office"
can
receive
constitutional
protection,
as can
"some
expressions
related
to
the
speaker's
job."226
But
the
Court
thought
the
distinguishing
feature
of
the
deputy
district
attorney's
memo
was
that
it
was
"made
pursuant
to
his
duties."
227
He
was
speaking
"as
a
prosecutor"
in
writing
the
memo,
not
as
a
citizen,
and
the
memo
"owes
its
existence
to
a
public
employee's
professional
responsibilities."
228
It
was
speech
"commissioned
or
created"
by
the
215.
Id.
at
147,
149.
216.
Id.
at
154.
217.
Id.
at
147-48.
218.
Id.
at
152.
219.
547
U.S.
410
(2006).
220.
Id.
at
410.
221.
Id.
at
413.
222.
Id.
at
415.
223.
Connick,
461
U.S.
at
147.
224.
Garcetti,
547
U.S.
at
422.
225.
Id.
at
419.
226.
Id.
at
420-21.
227.
Id.
at
421.
228.
Id.
494
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
employer.
2
29
He
was
performing
"the
tasks
he
was
paid
to
perform."
23
0
Even
if
the
content
of
the
memo
addressed
a
matter
of
public
concern,
it
was
outside
the
scope
of
First
Amendment
protection
because
it
was
made
"pursuant
to
official
responsibilities."
23
1
Garcetti
thus
added
to
the
threshold
question
in
evaluating
government-employee
speech.
To
receive
greater
constitutional
protection,
the
employee
must
not
only
be
speaking
about
a
matter
of
public
concern
but
must
also
be
speaking
in
their
private
capacity
as
a
citizen.
On
its
face,
Garcetti
is
debilitating
to
many
academic-freedom
claims
in
state
universities,
but
the
Court
added
an
important
proviso.
23
2
In
dissent,
Justice
David
Souter
highlighted
the
potential
implications
and
added,
"I
have
to
hope
that
today's
majority
does
not
mean
to
imperil
First
Amendment
protection
of
academic
freedom
in
public
colleges
and
universities,
whose
teachers
necessarily
speak
and
write
'pursuant
to
.
. .
official
duties."'
23
3
In
response,
Justice
Anthony
Kennedy,
writing
for
the
Court,
added
that
academic-
freedom
cases
might
be
different
and
"[w]e
need
not,
and
for
that
reason
do
not,
decide
whether
the
analysis
we
conduct
today
would
apply
in
the
same
manner
to
a
case
involving
speech
related
to
scholarship
or
teaching."
234
The
proviso
should
be
taken
seriously
most
obviously
because
it
explicitly
refrains
from
calling
into
question
the
"additional
constitutional
interests"
in
"academic
scholarship
or
classroom
instruction."
235
Moreover,
Kennedy
elsewhere
had
pointed
to
the
importance
of
the
anti-subversive
cases
in
establishing
the
critical
principle
that
the
danger
of
the
state
chilling
"individual
thought
and
expression"
was
"especially
real
in
the
University
setting,
where
the
State
acts
against
a
background
and
tradition
of
thought
and
experiment
that
is
at
the
center
of
our
intellectual
and
philosophical
tradition."
236
A
critical
question,
therefore,
is
how
Pickering
and
Garcetti
should
be
applied
to
legislative
regulation
of
academic
speech
in
state
229.
Id.
at
422.
230.
Id.
231.
Id.
at
424.
232.
The
Court's
opinion
has
nonetheless
created
confusion
about
how
to
think
about
the
professional
speech
of
professors.
A
recent
district
court
opinion,
for
example,
remarked
that
had
a
professor's
speech
been
"made
as
part
of
his
official
duties,
rather
than
as
a
citizen,
Garcetti
would
dictate
dismissal
of
his
retaliation
claim
....
But
it
is
undisputed
that
Hiers's
speech
was
not
part
of
his
official
duties,
so
Garcetti
does
not
apply
here."
Hiers
v.
Bd.
of
Regents,
No.
4:20-
CV-321-SDJ,
slip
op
at
6
n.2
(E.D.
Tex.
Mar.
11,
2022).
But
the
academic-freedom
proviso
seems
specifically
meant
to
preclude
such
a
result.
233.
Garcetti,
547
U.S.
at
438
(Souter,
J.,
dissenting).
234.
Id.
at
425.
235.
Id.
236.
Rosenberger
v.
Rector
&
Visitors,
515
U.S.
819,
835
(1995).
495
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
universities.
237
Such
regulations
would
force
courts
to
confront
precisely
the
question
that
the
Garcetti
Court
bracketed.
Professorial
speech
in
the
classroom
is
certainly
an
example
of
speech
made
pursuant
to
the
professor's
official
responsibilities
and
as
part
of
a
task
that
a
professor
is
paid
to
perform.
When
speaking
in
class,
a
professor
is
speaking
as
a
professor,
that
is,
as
a
government
employee,
not
as
a
citizen.
23
8
The
substantive
content
of
classroom
speech
might
well
be,
and
generally
is,
about
matters
of
public
concern,
but
Garcetti,
at
least
without
its
reservation
regarding
academic
freedom,
tells
us
that
is
not
enough
to
give
government-
employee
speech
constitutional
protection.
How
then
should
Pickering
and
Garcetti
be
understood
in
the
context
of
classroom
speech?
I
argue
that
academic
speech
should
be
understood
to
be
an
exception
to
the
Garcetti
framework.
Garcetti
can
only
be
reconciled
with
Keyishian
if
we
understand
that
the
particular
kind
of
speech
that
professors
are
employed
to
engage
in
as
part
of
their
job
responsibilities
is
speech
that
is
of
"special
concern
to
the
First
Amendment."
23
9
By
engaging
in
speech
as
a
professor,
these
particular
government
employees
are
engaging
in
speech
that
is
sheltered
by
the
First
Amendment,
even
though
that
is
not
true
in
the
case
of
other
government
employees
speaking
in
their
role
as
employees.
In
order
to
create
a
workable
doctrine
regarding
classroom
speech,
however,
it
is
important
to
understand
both
the
reasons
why
this
form
of
speech
as
an
employee
should
receive
237.
I
use
"academic
speech"
here
to
refer
broadly
to
professorial
speech
on
academic
matters,
whether
in
the
context
of
classroom
instruction,
scholarly
research,
or
scholarly
programming
on
and
off
campus.
All
such
speech
can
readily
be
understood
as
pursuant
to
a
professor's
professional
duties,
unlike
the
expression
of
private
opinions
in
an
extramural
context.
The
anti-CRT
proposals
thus
far
have
focused
particularly
on
classroom
speech
(whether
oral
discussion
or
classroom
materials),
but
it
is
not
hard
to
imagine
those
restrictions
being
extended
to
other
academic
contexts
and
the
core
academic-freedom
questions
would
be
the
same
whether
dealing
with
scholarship
or
teaching.
238.
It
should
be
noted
that
the
third
component
of
"academic
freedom"
laid
out
by
the
AAUP
is
when
professors
speak
"as
a
citizen"
in
extramural
or
intramural
settings.
See
STATEMENT
OF
PRINCIPLES,
supra
note
114,
at
14.
This
is
perhaps
more
properly
understood
as
falling
within
a
general
commitment
to
freedom
of
speech
rather
than
a
specific
theory
of
academic
freedom
as such.
When
speaking
"as
a
citizen"
about
matters
of
general
public
concern,
professors
are
no
differently
situated
than
other
government
employees.
It
is
when
speaking
"as
a
professor"
that
the
specific
constitutional
protections
for
academic
freedom
have
particular
significance.
See
Van
Alstyne,
supra
note
15,
at
142;
J.
Peter
Byrne,
Academic
Freedom:
A
"Special
Concern
of
the
First
Amendment,"
99
YALE
L.J.
251,
258
(1989);
David
M.
Rabban,
A
Functional
Analysis
of
"Individual"
and
"Institutional"
Academic
Freedom
under
the
First
Amendment,
53
LAw
&
CONTEMP.
PROBs.
227,
229
(1990);
Keith
E.
Whittington,
What
Can
Professors
Say
in
Public?
Extramural
Speech
and
the
First
Amendment,
73
CASE
W.
REs.
L.
REV.
(forthcoming
2023).
239.
Keyishian
v.
Bd.
of
Regents,
385
U.S.
589,
603
(1967).
496
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
protection
and
how
that
protection
can
be
appropriately
delimited
in
a
way
that
is
consistent
with
the
Court's
concerns
in
both
Garcetti
and
Keyishian.
We
should
begin
with
why
classroom
speech
is
not
like
a
disposition
memorandum.
Politicians
tried
to
suppress
professorial
expression
of
radical
ideas
in
the
mid-twentieth
century,
like
divisive
ideas
about
race
and
gender
today,
precisely
because
such
ideas
speak
to
matters
of
public
concern
and
are
politically
disfavored.
The
attempt
to
suppress
them
is
not
motivated
by
such
ordinary
concerns
as
ensuring
that
universities
operate
efficiently
but
rather
by
broad
political
motivations
regarding
what
ideas
politicians
believe
are
most
compatible
with
a
good
society.
The
desire
to
censor
such
ideas
on
campus
is
the
same
as
the
desire
to
censor
such
ideas
in the
public
sphere
more
broadly.
This
was
particularly
evident
in
the
case
of
the
anti-subversive
legislation,
when
regulations
of
professorial
speech
were
of a
piece
with
regulations
of
speech
more
generally.
As
the
Court's
First
Amendment
jurisprudence
gradually
made
it
clear
that
radical
ideas
as
expressed
by
ordinary
citizens
were
constitutionally
beyond
the
reach
of
politicians,
the
effort
to
suppress
such
speech
by
government
employees
lingered
until
the
Court
began
to
pare
back
those
efforts
as
well.
In
the
early
twenty-first
century,
it
is
clear
that
"Critical
Race
Theory"
or
"divisive
concepts"
could
not
be
erased
from
the
public
sphere
by
government
decree.
As a
consequence,
politicians
have
generally
240
focused
more
narrowly
on
domains
where
they
think
they
might
have
more
constitutional
leeway-
government
agencies,
241
public
schools,
242
public
libraries,
243
and
perhaps
state
universities.
244
The
government's
interest
in
censoring
speech
about
divisive
concepts
in
higher
education
raises
all
the
familiar
concerns
with
censorship
broadly
that
the
Court
has
systematically
rejected
since
the
early
years
of
the
twentieth
century.
Suppressing
divisive
concepts
in
higher
education
does
not
look
like
the
normal
work
of
an
employer
managing
the
workplace
but
instead
raises
Hugo
Black's
specter
of
"a
transient
majority"
trying
"to
select
the
ideas
people
can
think
about."
245
The
state's
interest
in
suppressing
a
professor's
speech
in
this
context
is
"not
significantly
greater
than
its
interest
in
limiting
a
similar
contribution
by
any
240.
There
are
some
exceptions.
See,
e.g.,
Hannah
Natanson,
Va.
Republicans
Seek
to
Limit
Sale
of
2
Books
in
Barnes
&
Noble
for
"Obscenity,"WASH.
POST
(May
20,
2022,
6:58 PM),
https://www.washingtonpost.com/education/2022/05/20/gender-queer-barnes-
and-noble/.
241.
See,
e.g.,
H.B.
2906,
55th
Leg.,
1st
Reg.
Sess.
(Ariz.
2021).
242.
See,
e.g.,
H.B.
2898,
55th
Leg.,
1st
Reg.
Sess.
(Ariz.
2021).
243.
See,
e.g., H.B.
2721,
110th
Gen.
Assemb.,
Reg.
Sess.
(Tenn.
2018).
244.
See,
e.g.,
H.B.
1012,
97th
Leg.,
Reg.
Sess.
(S.D.
2022).
245.
Adler
v.
Bd.
of
Educ.,
342
U.S.
485,
497
(1952)
(Black,
J.,
dissenting).
497
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
member
of
the
general
public."
246
Rather
than
reinforcing
the
logic
of
Connick
and
Garcetti
of
avoiding
the
constitutionalization
of
workplace
grievances,
allowing
Critical
Race
Theory
bans
to
stand
in
higher
education
would
be
anomalous
within
modern
First
Amendment
jurisprudence.
Protecting
academic
speech
from
the
undue
influence
of
politicians
is
close
to
the
heart
of
why
the
Court
responded
to
the
anti-
subversive
legislation
by
recognizing
a
constitutional
interest
in
academic
freedom
in
the
first
place.
It
was
not because
professors
had
unusually
interesting
things
to
say
when
opining
in
public
about
matters
far
distant
from
their
scholarly
expertise
that
the
justices
in
the
mid-twentieth
century
took
a
particular
interest
in
universities.
It
was
the
need
to
protect
free
inquiry
in
scholarship
and
the
classroom
that
the
Keyishian
Court
concluded
that
"[o]ur
Nation
is
deeply
committed
to
safeguarding
academic
freedom."
2
4
7
It
is
because
of
teaching
and scholarship
that
the
university
was
a
"center
of
independent
thought."
248
It
is
in
the
context
of
teaching
and
scholarship
that
Douglas
worried
about
"a
deadening
dogma"
taking
the
"place
of
free
inquiry."
249
The
"intellectual
life
of
a
university"
is
centrally
focused
on
its
academic
endeavors.
250
In
laying
down
constitutional
protections
for
academic
freedom,
the
justices
returned
again
and
again
to
the
importance
of
free
inquiry
in
the
classroom.
25
i
Most
obviously,
the
important
Sweezy
case
was
centered
in
part
on
a
political
investigation
of
the
content
of
a
lecture
to
a college
class,
an
area
in
which
the
Court
thought
the
"government
should
be
extremely
reticent
to
tread."
25 2
Universities
do
many things,
but
at
the
heart
of
a
university's
mission
is
the
effort
to
advance,
preserve,
and
communicate
knowledge.
253
Fulfilling
that
valuable
mission
requires
freedom
of
thought.
25
4
Academic
speech
is
by
design
communicative
to
a
broad
audience.
That
is
not
to
say
that
it
is
necessarily
accessible
to
or
of
interest
to
a
mass
audience.
Most
academic
speech
is
highly
specialized
and
is
fortunate
if
it
attracts
the
attention
of
even
a
specialized
audience.
But
it
is
central
to
the
academic
enterprise
to
disseminate
knowledge
246.
Pickering
v.
Bd.
of
Educ.,
391
U.S.
563,
573
(1968).
247.
Keyishian
v.
Bd.
of
Regents,
385
U.S.
589,
603
(1967).
248.
Wieman
v.
Updegraff,
344
U.S.
183,
197
(1952).
249.
Adler,
342 U.S.
at
510
(Douglas,
J.,
dissenting).
250.
Sweezy
v.
New
Hampshire,
354
U.S.
234,
261
(1957).
251.
See
Keyishian,
385 U.S.
at
603
(warning
of
a
"pall
of
orthodoxy
over
the
classroom");
Sweezy,
354
U.S.
at
250
("Teachers
and
students
must
always
remain
free
to
inquire,
to
study
and
to
evaluate,
to
gain
new
maturity
and
understanding;
otherwise
our
civilization
will
stagnate
and
die.").
252.
Sweezy,
354
U.S.
at
250.
253.
See
generally
KEITH
E.
WHITTINGTON,
SPEAK
FREELY
(2018).
254.
Id.
See
also
Keith
E.
Whittington,
Academic
Freedom
and
the
Mission
of
the
University,
59
Hous.
L.
REv.
821,
822
(2022).
498
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
to
others.
25
5
Teachers
in
the
classroom
are
seeking
to
impart
knowledge
to
a
body
of
students.
Scholars
producing
research
have
a
responsibility
to
share
the
fruits
of
their
research
with
others,
whether
those
others
are
expert
scholars
or
members
of
the
mass
public.
Academic
speech
is
concerned
not
only
with
advancing
and
preserving
knowledge
but
also
with
disseminating
it.
Distinctively
academic
speech
is
done
in
public
and
before
an
audience
in
a
way
that
is
quite
distant
from
a
lawyer
writing
a
memo
for
his
supervisor
and
in
a
way
that
distinguishes
it
from
the
kind
of
"expressions
made
at
work"
that
could
be
found
in
most
governmental
or
nongovernmental
offices.
25
6
The
Court
in
Garcetti
noted
that
whether
speech
took
place
in
public
or
in
the
office
is
not
"dispositive"
for
the
question
of
whether
it
is
protected
by
the
First
Amendment,
but
the
more
speech
resembles
speech
in
public
the
more
credibly
it
is
the
type
that
merits
First
Amendment
protection.
25
7
The
Court
in
Connick
clarified
that
constitutional
protections
for
government-employee
speech
depended
on
the
"content,
form,
and
context
of
a
given
statement."
258
The
content
of
academic
speech
is
255.
How
broad
or
narrow
the
audience
for
a
particular
example
of
professorial
speech
should
not
be
a
salient
factor
in
determining
whether
the
content
of
that
speech
involves
a
matter
of
public
concern
under
Pickering.
In
the
context
of
scholarly
communication,
matters
of
public
concern
are
probably
most
analogous
to
the
Court's
approach
to
obscenity
and
whether
a
given
expression
has
"serious
literary,
artistic,
political,
or
scientific
value."
Miller
v.
California,
413
U.S.
15,
24
(1973).
Esoteric
literary
criticism
or
technical
scientific
analysis
has
comparable
constitutional
value
for
academic-freedom
purposes
as
applied
ethics.
From
the
perspective
of
Keyishian,
it
would
be
equally
alarming
if
the
state
attempted
to
suppress
frequentist
statistical
analyses
because
it
favored
Bayesianism,
even
though
most
members
of
the
general
public
have
no
familiarity
with
either
school
of
thought.
Cf.
Heim
v.
Daniel,
No.
1:18-CV-836,
slip
op.
at
14
(N.D.N.Y.
May
10,
2022)
("Heim's
academic
writings
about
Keynesian
economic
concepts,
which
concern
complex
statistical
modeling
intended
for
consumption
by
a
relatively
narrow
audience,
do
not
qualify
as
speech
on
matters
of
'public
concern."').
256.
Garcetti
v.
Ceballos,
547
U.S.
410,
420
(2006).
257.
Id.
Certainly,
there
are
examples
of
speech
that
are
part
of
a
professor's
job
responsibilities
that
do
more
closely
resemble
the
kind
of
speech
at
issue
in
Connick
and
Garcetti.
Like
other
employees,
professors
write
memoranda,
reports,
performance
evaluations,
and
the
like,
and
such
speech
that
is
comparable
to
generic
employee
speech
is
traditionally
understood
to
fall
outside
the
scope
of
even
contractual
academic-freedom
protections.
While
there
are
border
cases
of
various
sort,
generally
speaking
the
more
professorial
speech
resembles
the
kind
of
speech
that
is
routinely
found
in
nonacademic
workspaces
the
less
the
justification
for
treating
it
as
academic
speech
that
is
special
under
the
First
Amendment.
See,
e.g.,
Demers
v.
Austin,
746
F.3d
402,
406
(9th
Cir.
2014)
(holding
that
a
faculty
member's
pamphlet
on
the
future
organization
of
the
communications
school
at
a
state
university
is
a
matter
of
public
concern
under
Pickering).
258.
Connick
v.
Myers,
461
U.S.
138,
147
(1983).
499
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
generally
a
matter
of
public
concern,
but
Connick
and
Garcetti
tell
us
that
is
not
sufficient.
Academic
speech
also
has
a
form
and
context,
however,
that
places
it
closer
to
traditional
public
speech.
Recognizing
academic
speech
as
constitutionally
protected
is
not
without
challenges.
In
particular,
the
courts
should
still
want
to
avoid
being
drawn
into
what
are
essentially
workplace
grievances,
even
when
those
grievances
involve
academic
speech.
The
central
concern
of
the
academic-freedom
cases
culminating
in
Keyishian
and
of
Pickering
balancing
of
government-employee
speech
is
to
insulate
academic
speech
from
outside
political
influence.
It
is
the
political
imposition
of
dogma
and
orthodoxy
that
is
of
constitutional
concern.
Courts
have,
quite
reasonably,
taken
a
highly
deferential
approach
to
claims
that
reduce
to
disagreements
about
the
scholarly
merits
of
faculty
hiring
and
promotion
cases,
for
example.
2 9
It
would
be
an
error
to
adopt
a
constitutional
standard
that
invites
judicial
oversight
of
how
such
internal
academic
affairs
are
resolved.
In
the
context
of
a
state
university,
academic
speech
by
professors
made
"pursuant
to
.
..
official
duties"
should
be
understood
to
be
constitutionally
protected.
26
0
For
most
government
employees,
Garcetti
holds
the
opposite,
that
employee
speech
loses
constitutional
protection
precisely
because
it
has
been
specifically
commissioned
by
a
governmental
employer.
But
professors
are
employed
to
perform
an
unusual
and
specific
role,
a
role
that
is
close
to
the
constitutional
enterprise.
They
are
employed,
in
part,
to
produce
and
disseminate
the
kind
of
ideas
that
are
of
public
interest
and
that
the
First
Amendment
is
understood
to
safeguard.
26
1
Recognizing
that
259.
See,
e.g.,
Allworth
v.
Howard
Univ.,
890
A.2d
194,
202
(D.C.
2006)
(giving
"deference
to
the
discretion
exercised
by
university
officials"
in
a
university
context);
Brown
v.
Trs.
of
Bos.
Univ.,
891
F.2d
337,
346
(1st
Cir.
1989)
("courts
must
take
special
care
to
preserve
the
University's
autonomy
in
making
lawful
tenure
decisions");
Keddie
v.
Pa.
State
Univ.,
412
F.
Supp.
1264,
1270
(M.D.
Pa.
1976)
("The
courts
will
not
serve
as
a
Super-Tenure
Review
Committee.");
McGill
v.
Regents
of
Univ.
of
Cal.,
52
Cal.
Rptr.
2d
466,,
471-73
(1996)
(adopting
an
arbitrary
and
capricious
standard
for
judging
a
denial
of
tenure
in
a
public
university);
Craine
v.
Trinity
Coll.,
791
A.2d
518,
536
(Conn.
2002)
("A
court
must
be
careful
not
to
substitute
its
judgment
improperly
for
the
academic
judgment
of
the
school.");
260.
Garcetti,
547
U.S.
at
438
(Souter,
J.,
dissenting).
261.
This
is
a
contingent
fact
about
American
universities.
It
is conceivable
that
a
state
could
radically
restructure
the
mission
of
a
state
university
such
that
its
faculty
were
not
engaged
in
free
inquiry
but
were
instead
expected
to
propagate
governmentally
approved
messages.
Under
such
circumstances,
academic
freedom
would
be
sharply
curtailed,
and
professors
would
be
more
analogous
to
public
school
teachers.
The
First
Amendment
values
associated
with
modern
American
universities
are
a
function
of
their
traditional
institutional
mission.
To
the
extent
that
states
have
currently
and
historically
committed
public
universities
to
such
a
mission,
then
First
Amendment
implications
follow
from
those
commitments.
500
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
government-employee
speech
crosses
that
threshold
does
not
end
the
judicial
inquiry.
A
court
would
still
need
to
consider
how
to
balance
the
First
Amendment
interest
against
the
government
employer's
legitimate
interests
in
managing
the
workplace.
26
2
Academic
speech
that
professors
are
"paid
to
perform"
comes
with
its
own
limits.
26
3
Professors
are
paid
to
perform
constitutionally
protected
speech,
but
not
all
professorial
speech
is
what
universities
have
commissioned.
Such
speech
might
better
be
regarded
as
private
speech
and
not
academic
speech
at
all.
That
is,
some
things
professors
say
while
"on
the
job"
and
in
the
workplace
are
not
examples
of
them
speaking
as
a
professor
but
of
them
speaking
as
a
private
citizen.
When
professors
are
engaging
in
academic
speech
in
the
context
of
scholarship
or
teaching,
the
First
Amendment
interest
in
protecting
such
speech
is
particularly
high.
The
question
then
becomes
what
legitimate
interests
the
state
has
in
regulating
such
speech
and
how
weighty
those
interests
are.
There
are
circumstances
in
which
the
state
has
recognizable
interests
in
managing
classroom
speech.
The
university
can
set
the
curriculum
and
can
expect
that
professorial
speech
in
the
classroom
will
be
both
germane
to
that
curriculum
and
professionally
competent.
When,
however,
professorial
speech
in
the
classroom
is
both
germane
and
professionally
competent,
the
state's
legitimate
interest
in
sanctioning
professors
for
such
speech
is
quite
low.
Viewpoint-based
discrimination
by
state
officials
far
removed
from
the
disciplinary
authorities
best
situated
to
assess
academic
speech
should
be
especially
suspect.
Traditional
principles
of
academic
freedom
are
understood
to
be
qualified,
not
absolute.
26
4
In
the
particular
context
of
classroom
speech,
faculty
speech
is
delimited
by
requirements
of
germaneness
and
professional
competence.
The
AAUP's
Statement
of
Principles
nods
to
the
germaneness
condition
by
noting
that
teachers
"should
be
careful
not
to
introduce
into
their
teaching
controversial
matter
which
has
no
relation
to
their
subject."
2
6 5
A
teacher
in
a
classroom
has
a
captive
audience
of
students,
which
creates
a
responsibility
on
the
part
of
the
teacher
not
to
abuse
that
captive
audience
with
262.
Traditional
Pickering
balancing
as
it
has
been
applied
by
the
courts
is
not
sufficiently
sensitive
to
the
unique
concerns
of
the
academic
context.
For
more
detail
of
how
Pickering
balancing
should
be
performed
when
professors
are
speaking
outside
the
scope
of
their
employment
duties,
see
Keith
E.
Whittington,
What
Can
Professors
Say
in
Public?
Extramural
Speech
and
the
First
Amendment,
73
WAKE
FOREST
L.
REV.
(forthcoming
2023).
The
considerations
discussed
there
are
applicable
to
the
context
of
speech
within
the
scope
of
their
employment
duties
as
well.
263.
Garcetti,
547
U.S.
at
422.
264.
See
Whittington,
supra
note
254,
at
829.
265.
STATEMENT
OF
PRINcIPLES,
supra
note
114,
at
14.
501
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
irrelevant
remarks.
Teachers
are
given a
privileged
platform
in
a
classroom
for
a
particular
purpose.
From
the
student's
perspective,
their
time is
not
to
be
frittered
away
with
speech
that
is
irrelevant
to
the
educational
purpose
of
the
class.
From
the
university's
perspective,
the
professional
duty
that
a
teacher
is
to
perform
is
to
instruct
students
in
the
subject
matter
of
the
class.
Teachers
who
spend
their
time
in
the
classroom
doing
something
else
are
not
performing
their
professional
duty and
as
a consequence
can
be
reasonably
sanctioned
by
the
university
for
that
malfeasance.
Courts
have
found
the
germaneness
standard
useful
for
assessing
how
much
protection
classroom
speech
should
receive,
and
they
have
had
to
make
similar
judgments
in
adjudicating
other
types
of
legal
claims.
In
Kracunas
v.
Iona
College,
2
66
for
example,
the
Second
Circuit
Court
of
Appeals
emphasized
that
"conduct
that
is
shown
to
be
harassment
(as
opposed
to
teaching)"
could
appropriately
be
sanctioned.
26 7
Although
the
college
raised
academic-freedom
concerns
that
might
arise
from
administrative
monitoring
of
how
professors
interact
with
students
as
they
perform
their
duties,
the
court
thought
that,
at
least
in
this
case,
both
university
officials
and
judges
could
assess
evidence
of
whether
professorial
conduct
"was
done
in
good
faith
as
a
part
of
his
teaching,
.. .
[or
could]
reasonably
be
seen
as
appropriate
to
further
a
pedagogical
purpose."
2
68
In
another
sexual
harassment
case
involving
"classroom
language,"
the
Sixth
Circuit
made
use
of
the
university's
own
harassment
policy
which
recognized
that
"speech
in
the
classroom
which
is
germane
to
course
content
is
not
subject
to
this
policy."
269
The
"unique
context"
of
"a
classroom
where
a
college
professor
is
speaking
to a
captive
audience
of
students"
both
raised
the
threat
of
professors
abusing
their
positions
to
harass
their
students
and
served
as
a
"unique
milieu
.. .
where
debate
and
the
clash
of
viewpoints
are
encouraged-
if
not
necessary-to
spur
intellectual
growth."
270
Where
classroom
speech
"was
found
to
serve
the
purpose
of
advancing
viewpoints,
however
repugnant,"
or
"had
as
their
purpose
influencing
or
informing
public
debate,"
then
it
merited
substantial
constitutional
protection.
271
The
governmental
employer's
interest
in
regulating
professorial
classroom
speech
that
is
not
"germane
to
the
course
266.
119
F.3d
80
(2d
Cir.
1997).
267.
Id.
at
88.
268.
Id.
The
court
recognized
that
there
will
be
cases
in
which
"the
line
between
pedagogy
and
harassment
will
be
difficult
to
draw,"
and
"the
use
of
these
legitimate
teaching
methods"
should
not
be
thrown
aside as
universities
and
courts
try
to
weed
out
sexual
harassment.
Id.
at
88
n.5.
269.
Bonnell
v.
Lorenzo,
241
F.3d
800,
818
n.10
(6th
Cir. 2001).
270.
Id.
at
820-21.
See
also,
Martin
v.
Parrish,
805
F.2d
583,
586
(5th
Cir.
1986)
(classroom
profanity
"constituted
a
deliberate,
superfluous
attack
on
a
'captive
audience' with
no
academic
purpose
or
justification").
271.
Bonnell,
241
F.3d
at
820.
502
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
content"
is
much
higher.
27
2
"[G]ratuitous
in-class"
speech
is
of
a
different
constitutional
nature
than
speech
that
was
a
legitimate
part
of
"an
academic
discussion."
273
It
should
be
noted
that
one
circuit
court
has
recently
suggested
that
germaneness
to
course
content
should
not
be
deemed
relevant
to
determining
what
professorial
classroom
speech
is
constitutionally
protected.
A
panel
of
the
Sixth
Circuit
resolved
a
case
involving
a
public
university's
pronoun
policy
as
applied
to
a
professor's
classroom
speech.
2
74
In
doing
so,
the
court
rejected
the
claim
that
there
was
no
"academic-freedom
exception
to
Garcetti"
and
that
governmental
employers
had
a
free
hand
to
regulate
professorial
classroom
speech.
275
The
court
thought
the
thrust
of
the
Supreme
Court's
decisions
growing
out
of
the
anti-subversive
controversies
had
established
that
"a
professor's
in-class
speech
to
his
students
is
anything
but
speech
by
an
ordinary
government
employee."
276
The
"need
for
the
free
exchange
of
ideas
in
the
college
classroom
is
unlike
that
in
other
public
workplace
settings."
27
7
The
court
was
emphatic
that
public
universities
do
not
have
a
license
to
act
as
classroom
thought
police.
They
cannot
force
professors
to
avoid
controversial
viewpoints
altogether
in
deference
to
a
state-
mandated
orthodoxy.
Otherwise,
our
public
universities
could
transform
the
next
generation
of
leaders
into
"closed-circuit
recipients
of
only
that
which
the
State
chooses
to
communicate."
27
8
So
far,
so
good.
At
one
point,
however,
the
court
characterized
that
academic-
freedom
exception
as
covering
"all
classroom
speech
related
to
matters
of
public
concern,
whether
that
speech
is
germane
to
the
contents
of
the
lecture
or
not."
2
79
It
is
not
clear
that
the
court
thought
the
germaneness
issue
was
relevant
to
resolving
the
case before
it,
and
the
court
never
explicitly
referred
to
germaneness
beyond
this
brief
mention.
The
court
specifically
noted
that
"some
classroom
speech
falls
outside
the
[Garcetti
academic-freedom]
exception,"
272.
Id.
at
819.
273.
Hardy
v.
Jefferson
Cmty.
Coll.,
260
F.3d
671,
679
(6th
Cir.
2001).
274.
Meriwether
v.
Hartop,
992
F.3d
492,
507
(6th
Cir.
2021).
The
state
university
adopted
a
policy
requiring
that
university
officials,
including
professors,
refer
to
students
by
their
"preferred
pronoun[s]"
reflecting
the
students'
"self-asserted
gender
identity."
Id.
at
498.
275.
Id.
at
506.
276.
Id.
at
507.
277.
Id.
278.
Id.
(quoting
Tinker
v.
Des
Moines
Indep.
Cmty.
Sch.
Dist.,
393
U.S.
503,
511
(1969)).
279.
Id.
503
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
including
"non-ideological
ministerial"
speech
that
professors
might
be
called
upon
to
make
in
the
classroom.
280
Moreover,
the
court
was
also
concerned
with
arguing
that
the
instructor's
selection
of
pronouns
to
be
used
in
the
classroom
conveyed
a
salient
"message."
281
This
particular
case
involved
a
philosophy
professor
teaching
courses
on
political
philosophy,
ethics,
and
the
history
of
Christian
thought,
and the
university's
directives
extended
to
restricting
the
professor
from
stating
his
views
on
the
pronoun
policy
in
his
course
syllabus.
282
The
court
also
thought
that
the
professor's
speech
had
not
"inhibited
his
duties
in
the
classroom."
28
3
The
court's
extension
of
the
academic-
freedom
exception
to
classroom
speech
whether
or
not
"that
speech
is
germane"
is
not clearly
rooted
in
the
broader jurisprudence
regarding
academic
freedom,
was
not
specifically
explained
or
justified
by
the
court,
and
may
not
have
been
necessary
to resolving
this
particular
case.
2 84
Casting
aside
a
germaneness
requirement
risks
tying
the
hands
of
university
officials
to
address
problems
with
how
professors
treat
their
captive
audience
and
even
with
whether
they
are
performing
their
core
duties,
which
do
not
primarily
include
sharing
with
students
in
class
the
professor's
"core
religious
and
philosophical
beliefs."
285
Such
a
move
should
not
be
necessary
to
resolving
the
main
issues
associated
with
the recent
anti-CRT
policies
either,
since
in
many
cases
they
would
implicate
classroom
speech
that
is
germane
to
the
subject
matter
of
the
course.
Whether
university
officials,
or
state
legislatures,
could
reasonably
take
action
against
professors
who
unnecessarily
introduce
into
their
classes
controversial
content
that
is
not
germane
to
their
subject
matter
can
be
put
off
to
another
day.
286
A
second
condition
on
professorial
speech
in the
classroom
is
that
it
be
professionally
competent.
The
professional
duty
of
the
instructor
in
the
classroom
is
to
provide
professionally
competent
instruction.
That
is
the
type
of
speech
professors
are
commissioned
to
perform,
and
it
is
the
type
of
speech
both
students
and
university
officials
can
280.
Id.
281.
Id.
at
508.
282.
Id.
at
498,
500.
283.
Id.
at
511.
It
is
not
obvious
that
the
court's
judgment
about
the
application
of
those
principles
to
the
facts
of
this
case
is
fully
justified.
The
university
employer's
interest
in
how
professors
address
students
in
the
classroom
is
relatively
strong.
284.
Id.
at
507.
The
court
briefly
noted
that
this
pronoun
policy
also
raised
issues
of
"compelled
speech
on a
matter
of
public
concern,"
but
did not rely
on
it.
Id.
at
510.
Policies
that
compel
professors
to
say
things
in
the
classroom
that
they
do
not
believe
raise
distinct
constitutional
problems,
but
such
problems
are
generally
not
immediately
relevant
to
the
anti-CRT
context.
285.
Id.
at
509.
286.
That
is
to
say,
there
may
be
important
constitutional
differences
between
critical
race
theory being
discussed
in
a
chemistry
class
and
in
an
African
American
studies
class.
504
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
reasonably
expect
to
receive.
It
is
entailed
within
the
scope
of
academic
freedom
that
a
professor
might
introduce
students
to
radical,
marginal,
or
not
widely
accepted
ideas,
but
an
instructor
has
a
responsibility
to
ensure
that
students
recognize
the
context
of
those
ideas
and
how
they
fit
within
the
broader
body
of
knowledge.
A
professor
who
routinely
presented
to
students
as
mainstream
and
correct
ideas
that
are
in
fact
roundly
rejected
by
experts
in
the
field
or
a
professor
who
routinely
conveys
a
false
understanding
of
what
the
state
of
knowledge
within
a
field
of
study
might
be
is
not
conducting
themselves
in
a
professionally
competent
manner.
Academic
freedom
has
value
to
the
extent
that
it
protects
professionally
competent
speech.
If
it
instead
becomes
a
mechanism
for
shielding
instructors
peddling
proverbial
snake
oil
to
their
students,
then
it
serves
no
social
function.
A
civil
engineering
professor
who
teaches
students
in
such
a
way
that
bridges
that
they
built
would
fall
down
rather
than
stay
upright
is
not
protected
by
academic
freedom.
Universities
could
reasonably
sanction
professors
for
indulging
in
such
classroom
speech
without
raising
constitutional
concerns.
28
7
Professional
competence
both
conditions
and
underwrites
protections
for
academic
freedom.
The
founding
statement
of
the
AAUP,
the
1915
Declaration
of
Principles,
called
for
greater
security
of
tenure
in
order
to
give
scholars
and
teachers
the
independence
necessary
to
engage
in
free
inquiry
without
fear
of
reprisal
for
reaching
unpopular
or
inconvenient
conclusions.
288
The
AAUP
recognized,
however,
that
"there
are
no
rights
without
corresponding
duties."
28
9
It
is
only
those
"who
carry
on
their
work
in
the
temper
of
the
scientific
inquirer
who
may
justly
assert
this
claim"
to
freedom
of
teaching.
290
A
professor
who
seeks
to
indoctrinate
rather
than
teach
cannot
legitimately
hide
behind
a
claim
of
a freedom
to
teach.
In
the
words
of
that
1915
Declaration,
"his
business
is
not
to
provide
his
students
with
ready-made
conclusions,
but
to
train
them
to
think
for
themselves,
and
to
provide
them
access
to
those
materials
which
they
need
if
they
are
to
think
intelligently."
2
91
A
professor
who
fails
in
that
task
should
not
be
sheltered
from
discipline,
and
287.
For
doubts
about
constitutionalizing
individual
academic
freedom
because
of
the
problem
of
judges
assessing
the
quality
of
scholarly
work,
see
generally
Lawrence
Rosenthal,
Does
the
First
Amendment
Protect
Academic
Freedom?,
46
J.
COLL.
&
UNIV.
L.
223
(2021).
288.
AM.
Ass'N
OF
UNIV.
PROFESSORS,
DECLARATION
OF
PRINCIPLES
ON
ACADEMIC
FREEDOM
AND
TENURE
300
(1915)
[hereinafter
DECLARATION
OF
PRINCIPLES],
https://www.aaup.orgNR/rdonlyres/A6520A9D-OA9A-4
7
B
3
-B
5
5
0-
C006B5B224E7/0/1915Declaration.pdf.
289.
Id.
at
298.
290.
Id.
291.
Id.
505
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
[i]f
this
profession
should
prove
itself
unwilling
to
purge
its
ranks
of
the
incompetent
and
the
unworthy,
or
to
prevent
the
freedom
which
it
claims
in the
name
of
science
from
being
used
as a
shelter
for
inefficiency,
for
superficiality,
or
for
uncritical
and
intemperate
partisanship,
it
is
certain
that
the
task
will
be
performed
by
others.
292
In
responding
to
the
anti-subversive
push
of
the
McCarthy
era,
the
AAUP
laid
out
what
should
qualify
as
good
cause
to
terminate
a
member
of
the
faculty.
"Action
against
a
faculty
member
cannot
rightly
be
taken
on
grounds
that
limit
his
freedom
as
an
individual,
as
a
member
of
the
academic
community,
or
as
a
teacher
and
scholar."
293
Terminating
a
professor
merely
for
engaging
in
politically
unpopular
speech,
whether
in
the
classroom
or
in
scholarship,
is
hardly
consistent
with
such
an
aspiration.
Removal
from
the
faculty
merely
for
being
a
member
of
the
Communist
Party,
for
example,
would
violate
those
principles.
29
4
"Removal
can
be
justified
only
on
the
ground,
established
by
evidence,
of
unfitness
to
teach
because
of
incompetence,
lack
of
scholarly
objectivity
or
integrity,
serious
misuse
of
the
classroom
or
of
academic
prestige,
gross
personal
misconduct,
or
conscious
participation
in
conspiracy
against
the
government."
295
Professionally
competent
speech
merits
protection,
even
if
it
is
unpopular
or
controversial.
Professionally
incompetent
speech
merits
sanction,
even
if
it
is
popular
or
conformist.
As
Robert
Post
has
highlighted,
professional
competence
is
not
only
a
standard
that
the
individual
faculty
member
must
meet
but
one
that
the
profession
must
enforce.
It
is
also
a
standard
that
government
officials
cannot
appropriately
abrogate.
"[W]e
should
expect,"
he
notes,
"to
see
First
Amendment
coverage
triggered
whenever
government
seeks
by
.
..
legislation
to
disrupt
the
communication
of
accurate
expert
knowledge."
296
He
observes
that
courts
have
rebuffed
legislation
that
requires,
for
example,
medical
providers
"to
give
untruthful,
misleading
and
irrelevant
information
to
patients."
297
Such
governmental
requirements
that
professional
speech
be
incompetent
so
as
to
better
satisfy
political
sensibilities
implicates
First
Amendment
rights.
298
As
one
court
noted,
"the
State
cannot
compel
an
individual
simply
to
speak
the
State's
ideological
message,"
though
it
can
reasonably
require
professionals
to
convey
292.
Id.
293.
Am.
Ass'n
of
Univ.
Professors,
Academic
Freedom
and
Tenure
in
the
Quest
for
National
Security,
42
AM.
ASS'N
UNIV.
PROFESSORS
BULL.
49,
57
(1956).
294.
Id.
at
58.
295.
Id.
296.
ROBERT
C.
POST,
DEMOCRACY,
EXPERTISE,
ACADEMIC
FREEDOM:
A
FIRST
AMENDMENT
JURISPRUDENCE
FOR
THE
MODERN
STATE
48
(Yale
Univ.
Press
2012).
297.
Id.
298.
Planned
Parenthood
of
the
Heartland
v.
Heineman,
724
F.
Supp.
2d
1025,
1048
(D.
Neb.
2010).
506
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
"truthful"
and
"relevant"
information.
299
The
Supreme
Court
has
recently
pointed
out
that,
"[a]s
with
other
kinds
of
speech,
regulating
the
content
of
professionals'
speech
'pose
[s]
the
inherent
risk
that
the
Government
seeks
not
to
advance
a
legitimate
regulatory
goal,
but
to
suppress
unpopular
ideas
or
information.'
30
0
Whether
the
state
compels
a
professional
to
communicate
information
that
the
professional
community
believes
is
untrue
or
prohibits
a
professional
from
communicating
information
that
the
professional
community
believes
is
true,
the
result
is
that
the
state
is
substituting
its
own
ideological
commitments
for
the
free
pursuit
of
truth
by
the
relevant
experts.
For
the
state
to
require
professorial
speech
in
the
classroom
to
be
incompetent,
whether
by
omission
or
commission,
it
would
vitiate
the
value
that
academic
freedom
under
the
First
Amendment
is
intended
to
provide
to
society.
Professorial
classroom
speech
that
is
neither
germane
to
the
class
nor
professionally
competent
is
deserving
of
little
constitutional
protection.
Note,
however,
that
such
speech
might
still
be
on
matters
of
public
concern.
A
chemistry
professor
who
spends
his
class
time
talking
about
the
presidential
election
or
a
medical
professor
who
instructs
his
class
that
vaccines
cause
autism
might
well
be
engaging
in
speech
that
in
other
circumstances
would
be
entitled
to
robust
constitutional
protection.
A
professor
who
indulges
in
such
speech
on
their
private
blog
on
their
own
time
would
enjoy
some
presumptive
protection
under
Pickering.
30
1
We
can
imagine
four
separate
scenarios
of
professorial
speech
in
a
state
university
to
clarify
how
Pickering,
Garcetti,
and
the
constitutionalized
protection
for
academic
freedom
referenced
in
Keyishian
would
interact.
The
examples
demonstrate
how
the
three
cases
can
be
reconciled
to
simultaneously
protect
free
inquiry
into
controversial
ideas
in
a
university
setting
and
the
efficient
functioning
of
a
university
as
a
particular
kind
of
state
agency.
299.
Planned
Parenthood
Minn.,
N.
Dakota,
S.
Dakota
v.
Rounds,
530
F.3d
724,
734-35
(8th
Cir.
2008).
300.
Nat'l
Inst.
of
Fam.
&
Life
Advocs.
v.
Becerra,
138
S.
Ct.
2361,
2374
(2018)
(alteration
in
original)
(quoting
Turner
Broad.
Sys.,
Inc.
v.
FCC,
512
U.S.
622,
641
(1994)).
301.
Private
extramural
speech
that
is
professionally
incompetent
might
well
raise
questions
about
professional
fitness
for
an
academic
position.
The
AAUP
emphasizes
that
extramural
speech
should
not
be
the
sole
basis
for
determining
that
a
professor
is
professionally
unfit,
but
it
might
well
lead
a
university
to,
for
example,
take
a
closer
look
at
that
faculty
member's
scholarship
and
classroom
speech,
to
ensure
that
it
is
professionally
competent.
AM.
ASS'N
OF
UNIv.
PROFESSORS,
Committee
A
Statement
on
Extramural
Utterances,
in
PoLICY
DOCUMENTS
AND
REPORTS
31,
31
(Johns
Hopkins
Univ.
Press
11th
ed.
2015)
("Extramural
utterances
rarely
bear
upon
the
faculty
member's
fitness
for
continuing
service.
Moreover,
a
final
decision
should
take
into
account
the
faculty
member's
entire
record
as
a
teacher
and
scholar.").
507
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
Scenario
1:
A
law
school
professor
teaching
a
class
on
race
and
American
law
conducts
a
classroom
discussion
of
core
ideas
associated
with
the
scholarly
literature
on
Critical
Race
Theory
and
in
the
process
distributes
class
materials
and
advocates
ideas
that
run
afoul
of
legislative
proposals
curtailing
the
introduction
of
divisive
concepts
into
university
classes.
Such
classroom
speech
would
fall
squarely
within
the
domain
of
speech
made
pursuant
to
official
duties.
But
for
an
academic-freedom
exception,
Garcetti
would
allow
government
officials
to
suppress
such
speech.
A
proper
academic
freedom-exception,
however,
would
recognize
such
speech
as
robustly
protected
under
Keyishian.
The
anti-CRT
bills
would
be
a
viewpoint-discriminatory
interference
with
constitutionally
protected
speech,
which
should
weigh
heavily
in
favor
of
the
professor.
Indeed,
the
anti-CRT
bills
look
like
precisely
the
kind
of
prior
restraint
through
"sweeping
statutory
impediment
to
speech"
that
the
Court
has
said
is
particularly
disfavored
even
within
a
government
employment
context.
302
If
a
court
were
to
engage
in
a
balancing
exercise
as
suggested
by
the
Pickering
framework,
the
government
would
have
a
heavy
burden
to
bear
in
demonstrating
that
a
statutory
prior
restraint
on
the
expression
of
certain
viewpoints
in
a
university
classroom
is
justified.
The
professor
in
this
scenario
is
engaging
in professionally
competent
speech
appropriate
to
the
subject
matter
of
the
course.
By
attempting
to
restrain
professors
from
engaging
in
such
speech,
the
state
legislature
would
not
simply
be
attempting
to
specify
the
curriculum
of
the
university.
It
would
be
attempting
to
legislate
what
can
be
said
when
teaching
that
curriculum.
The
state
sanctions
teaching
certain
course
content,
but
here
it
also
demands
an
orthodoxy
on
how
that
content
is
understood.
Professors
are
free
to
discuss
controversies
regarding
race,
but
only
if
they
toe
the
legislature's
line
on
how
those
controversies
are
to
be
viewed.
It
is
precisely
such
an
imposition
of
orthodoxy
in
higher
education
that
the
Court
regarded
as
repugnant
to
the
Constitution.
Scenario
2:
A
law
school
professor
teaching
a
class
on
contracts
regularly
spends
large
portions
of
the
class
time
discussing
recent
political
events
and
hosting
guest
lecturers
to
advocate
for
the
professor's
pet
political
causes.
Such
classroom
speech
is
not
made
pursuant
to
official
duties
since
no
professor
is
employed
for
the
purpose
of
sharing
political
opinions
with
a
captive
audience
of
students
to
the
exclusion
of
the
course
material
that
students
are
supposed
to
be
learning.
It
does,
however,
take
advantage
of
the
privileged
access
to
the
student's
time
that
a
professor
has
as
a
consequence
of
his
state
employment.
Lecturing
to
students
was
"within
the
scope
of
an
employee's
302.
United
States
v.
Nat'l
Treasury
Emps.
Union,
513
U.S.
454, 467
(1995).
508
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
duties,"
30 3
but
lecturing
to
students
about
his
personal
political
beliefs
was
not.
The
content
of
such
private
speech
does
involve
"commenting
upon
matters
of
public
concern,"
however,
and
Pickering
would
suggest
that
it
would
be
necessary
"to
arrive
at
a
balance
between
the
interests
of
the
teacher, as
a
citizen,
. . .
and
the
interest
of
the
State,
as
an
employer,
in
promoting
the
efficiency
of
the
public
services
it
performs
through
its
employees."
304
However,
the
timing
and
circumstances
of
such
speech
weighs
heavily
in
favor
of
the
state
as
an
employer
restricting
it.
Pickering
itself
emphasized
that
a
letter
to
the
editor
of
a
newspaper
could
not
"be
presumed
to
have
in
any
way
.
..
impeded
the
teacher's
proper
performance
of
his
daily
duties."
3
05
Departing
from
assigned
duties
in
order
to
engage
in
private
political
speech,
on
the
other
hand,
implicates
the
need
of
the
public
employer
to
"be
able
to
control
the
operations
of
its
workplace."
3
06
A
state-university
employer
has
a
strong
interest
in
preventing
a
professor
from
imposing
on
a
captive
audience
of
students
speech
"with
no
academic
purpose
or
justification."
307
A
germaneness
test
for
professorial
classroom
speech
distinguishes
between
the
kind
of
speech
that
is
properly
protected
by
the
First
Amendment
concerns
raised
in
Keyishian
and
the
kind
of
speech
that
interferes
with
the
delivery
of
the
public
services
that
the
state
has
an
interest
in
maintaining.
Scenario
3:
A
political
science
professor
teaching
a
class
on
campaigns
and
elections
in
American
politics
dedicates
the
semester
to
expounding
on
his
belief
that
Italian
defense
firms
use
satellites
to
change
American
vote
tallies,
that
Venezuela
manipulates
American
voting
machines,
and
that
North
Korea
smuggles
into
American
ballot
boxes
counterfeit
paper
ballots
produced
in
China.
Unlike
the
private
speech
at
issue
in
Scenario
2,
the
classroom
speech
in
this
situation
is
indeed
pursuant
to
the
professor's
duties.
The
professor
is
commissioned
to
lecture
to
students
about
how
elections
operate
in
the
United
States,
and
that
is
what
the
professor
303.
Lane
v.
Franks,
573
U.S.
228,
240
(2014).
304.
Pickering
v.
Bd.
of
Educ.,
391
U.S.
563,
568
(1968).
305.
Id.
at
572.
306.
Helget
v.
City
of
Hays,
844
F.3d
1216,
1221
(10th
Cir.
2017)
(citing
Pickering,
391
U.S.
at
568).
See
also
Miller
v.
Clinton
Cnty.,
544
F.3d
542,
547
(3d
Cir.
2008)
("public
employers
are
still
employers,
and
they
therefore
have
the
same
concern
for
efficiency
and
the
need
to
review
and
evaluate
employees
as
any
other
employer
in
order
to
ensure
that
the
actions
of
employees
do
not
interfere
with
the
performance
of
public
functions.")
(citing
Rankin
v.
McPherson,
483
U.S.
378,
383-89
(1987));
Dougherty
v.
Sch.
Dist.
of
Phila.,
772
F.3d
979,
987
(3d
Cir.
2014)
("the
Supreme
Court
also
aptly
recognizes
the
government's
countervailing
interest-as
an
employer-in
maintaining
control
over
their
employees'
words
and
actions
for
the
proper
performance
of
the
workplace")
(citing
Garcetti
v.
Ceballos,
547
U.S.
410,
418-19
(2006)).
307.
Martin
v.
Parrish,
805
F.2d
583,
586
(5th
Cir.
1986).
509
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
is
doing.
The
trouble
is
that
the
professor
is
performing
those duties
in an
incompetent
fashion
by
conveying
to
students
ideas
that
are
roundly
rejected
within
the
relevant
expert
community
and
conveying
them
as
if
they
enjoyed
scholarly
validity.
The
state's
interest
in
excluding
such
speech
from
the
classroom
is
just
as
real,
even
though
it
bears
a
closer
relationship
to
the
kind
of
speech
the
academic-freedom
cases
are
concerned
with
protecting.
Even
when
government-employee
speech
merits
First
Amendment
protection,
the
government
still
has
an
"employer's
legitimate
interest[]
in
its
mission."
3
08
The
core
mission
of
the
university
is
truth-seeking,
which
it
advances
by
nurturing
a
scholarly
community
capable
of
building
up
expert
knowledge
through
a
process
of
inquiry
governed
by
disciplinary
norms
and
ways
of
testing
and
evaluating
claims.
309
Both
the
field
of
accepted
knowledge
and
the
modes
of
proceeding
in
advancing
knowledge
are
subject
to
change
within
a
vibrant
scholarly
enterprise.
Ideas
that
were
once
accepted
get
rejected
over
time.
Modes
of
inquiry
that
were
once
taken
seriously
get
discarded
as
unreliable.
Academia
gives
a
great
deal
of
leeway
to
individual
scholars
to
test
those
boundaries
on
the
assumption
that
fields
of
scholarly
inquiry
should
always
hold
themselves
open
to
legitimate
challenge.
But
there
are
still
limits,
and
a
great
deal
of
scholarly
activity
is
expended in
evaluating the
quality
of
research
and
of
scholars
and
making
determinations
about
what
to
embrace
and
what
to
reject.
Scholarly
assessments
of
the
substantive
quality
of
scholarly
writing
and
teaching
have
always
been
accepted
as
consistent
with
academic-freedom
principles.
A
key
consideration
is
who
is
making
such
an
assessment.
The
AAUP
has
long
emphasized
that
academic
freedom
is
endangered
if
such
judgments
are
made
by
nonscholars,
whether
legislators
or
boards
of
trustees.
3
10
Even
when
fellow
scholars
are
making
such
judgments,
we
might
still
worry
that
scholarly
assessments
can
become
a
mere
pretext
for
exercising
power
for
inappropriate
ends,
whether
racial
or
sexual
discrimination
or
political
hostility.
Academic-freedom
principles
do
not
exclude
the
need
for
such
basic
judgments
of
whether
to
confer
a
scholarly
degree
on
a
student
or
whether
to
employ
or
promote
a
potential
member
of
the
faculty.
308.
Engquist
v.
Or.
Dep't
of
Agric.,
478
F.3d
985,
994
(9th
Cir. 2007).
See
also
City
of
San
Diego
v.
Roe,
543
U.S.
77,
82
(2004)
("the
government
employer's
right
to
protect
its
own
legitimate
interests
in
performing
its
mission").
309.
WHITTINGTON,
supra
note
253,
at
7.
310.
DECLARATION
OF
PRINCIPLES,
supra
note
288,
at
294
("[T]he
proper
fulfillment
of
the
work
of
the
professoriate
requires
that
our
universities
shall
be
so
free
that
no
fair-minded
person
shall
find any
excuse
for
even
a
suspicion
that
the
utterances
of
university
teachers
are
shaped
or
restricted
by
the
judgment,
not
of
professional
scholars,
but
of
inexpert
and
possibly
not
wholly
disinterested
persons
outside
of
their
ranks.").
510
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
In
the
specific
context
of
government-employee
speech,
courts
have
likewise
recognized
that
the
need
to
make
such
judgments
weigh
in
the
balance
on
the
side
of
governmental
interests.
When
engaged
in
a
Pickering
balancing
of
interests,
courts
have
noted
that
even
constitutionally
protected
employee
speech
might
"reflect
upon
the
employee's
competence
to
perform
his
or
her
job."
31
1
Government
employers
are
"entirely
justified"
in
"evaluating
the
soundness"
of
employees'
speech
when
that
speech
is
relevant
to
their
job
functions.
3
12
Determining
whether
an
employee
displays
"a
lack
of
professional
competence"
is
an
unavoidable
aspect
of
the
government
acting
in
its
role
as
an
employer,
and
that
need
does
not
evaporate
when
the
speech
in
question
occurs
in
a
classroom
setting
or
has
First
Amendment
relevance.
3
13
"[C]lassroom
performance"
is
within
the
scope
of
an
employer's
interest.
314
Even
given
robust
First
Amendment
protection
for
academic
freedom,
state
universities
retain
the
ability
to
dismiss
the
historian
of
twentieth-century
European
history
who
insists
on
instructing
his
students
that
the
Holocaust
is
a
myth
or
the
astronomer
who
requires
his
students
to
learn
that
the
sun
revolves
around
the
earth.
31
5
Scenario
4:
A
group
of
professors
eating
lunch
in
a
faculty
lounge
on
campus
get
into
a
spirited
discussion
about
the
role
of
race
in
American
society
in
which
one
loudly
proclaims
the
truth
of
ideas
banned
by
legislation
aimed
at
excluding
divisive
concepts
from
higher
education.
A
portion
of
the
conversation
is
recorded
by
a
passing
student
and
posted
on
social
media,
resulting
in
demands
from
state
political
leaders
that
the
professor
be
fired.
Such
a
case
falls
neatly
within
a
traditional
Pickering
framework.
Although
the
speech
at
issue
here
takes
place
on
the
job
site
rather
than
in
an
extramural
context,
the
speech
is
clearly
private
and
not
part
of
the
ordinary
duties
of
a
professor.
The
professor
in
this
context
is
acting
as
a
citizen,
not
as
a
government
employee.
Moreover,
the
speech
relates
to
matters
of
public
concern,
and
thus
passes
the
threshold
question
of
whether
they
are
entitled
to
constitutional
consideration.
The
question
then
becomes
whether
the
state
as
an
employer
has
a
sufficiently
weighty
countervailing
interest
in
restricting
such
speech.
Private
remarks
in
ordinary
workplace
conversations
diminish
the
state's
interest
in
regulating
such
speech
unless
it
311.
Koch
v.
Hutchinson,
847
F.2d
1436,
1442
(10th
Cir.
1988).
312.
Egger
v.
Phillips,
710
F.2d
292,
317
(7th
Cir.
1983).
313.
Id.
at
318.
314.
Wren
v.
Spurlock,
798
F.2d
1313,
1318
(10th
Cir.
1986).
315.
On
academic-freedom
principles
and
professional
incompetence,
see
Brian
G.
Brooks,
Adequate
Cause
for
Dismissal:
The
Missing
Element
in
Academic
Freedom,
22
J.
COLL.
&
UNIV.
L.
331,
331-32
(1995);
David
M.
Rabban,
The
Regrettable
Underenforcement
of
Incompetence
as
Cause
to
Dismiss
Tenured
Faculty,
91
IND.
L.J.
39,
42
(2015).
511
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
directly
"interfered
with
the
efficient
functioning
of
the
office."
3
1
6
The
faculty
lounge
is
recognized
as
a
place
"where
professors
regularly
talk
about
political
and
social
issues
with
one
another"
and
where
the
state
employer's
interest
in
regulating
the
content
of
the
ideas
expressed
is
quite
limited.
3
17
The
fact
that
the
speech
was
to
a
small
audience
and
"in-house"
might
be
"considered
in
determining
whether
the
speech
addressed
a
matter
of
public
concern,"
but
it
does
not
in
itself
heighten
the
state's
legitimate
interest
in
punishing
such
speech.
318
Pickering
is
most
helpful
in
thinking
about
government-employee
speech
that
does
not
involve
the
employee's
duties
as
an
employee.
When
a
professor
is
speaking
"as
a
citizen,"
whether
outside
the
workplace
or
even
in
the
workplace,
then
the
Pickering
framework
usefully
identifies
the
considerations
at
play
when
governmental
employers
attempt
to
sanction
such
speech.
31
9
It
is
less
helpful,
however,
in
identifying
when
speech
should
be
protected
or
what
considerations
ought
to
be
relevant
to
the
employer's
actions
when
a
professor
is
performing
his
or
her
duties
as
a
professor.
Garcetti
establishes
that
government
employees
outside
the
educational
context
have
few
First
Amendment
rights
when
performing
their
duties
but
provides
little
guidance
for
the
educational
context.
Garcetti
raises,
but
does
not
answer,
the
question
of
how
the
courts
should
address
First
Amendment
claims
raised
by
professorial
speech
that
is
pursuant
to
their
official
duties.
When
grappling
with
the
anti-subversive
legislation
of
the
mid-
twentieth
century,
the
Court
came
to
appreciate
the
extent
to
which
the
speech
that
professors
routinely
engage
in
as
part
of
their
academic
duties,
in
both
their
scholarly
activities
and
in
the
classroom,
is
central
to
the
First
Amendment.
The
Court
cannot
now
allow
state
legislatures
to
restrict
the
set
of
ideas
professors
are
allowed
to
discuss
in
the
classroom
or
the
viewpoint
that
professors
adopt
relative
to
those
ideas
without
repudiating
those
hard-won
lessons.
While
most
government
employees
enjoy
their
greatest
constitutional
protection
when
speaking
in
their
private
capacity
as
citizens,
as
the
Court
recognized
in
Pickering,
university
professors
are
distinctive
in
requiring
constitutional
protection
for
their
speech
as
government
employees.
To
effectuate
the
insight
that
academic
freedom
is
of
"a
special
concern
to
the
First
Amendment,"
320
the
Court
would
need
to
insulate
classroom
speech
from
legislative
intrusions
that
serve
a
primary
purpose
of
attempting
to
control
what
ideas
are
316.
Rankin
v.
McPherson,
483
U.S.
378,
389
(1987).
317.
Hiers
v.
Bd.
of
Regents,
No.
4:20-CV-321-SDJ,
slip
op
at
25
(E.D.
Tex.
Mar.
11,
2022).
318.
Davis
v.
W.
Cmty.
Hosp.,
755
F.2d
455,
461
(5th
Cir.
1985).
319.
Pickering
v.
Bd.
of
Educ.,
391
U.S.
563,
568
(1968).
320.
Keyishian
v.
Bd.
of
Regents,
385
U.S.
589,
603
(1967).
512
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
discussed
and
taken
seriously
in
the
public
sphere.
The
fact
that
some
professors
are
government
employees
does
not
eliminate
their
First
Amendment
interest
in
being
able
to
teach
students
ideas
that
may
be
controversial
and
out
of
favor
with
incumbent
government
officials
but
that
are
germane
to
their
classes
and
within
the
realm
of
professional
competence.
The
state
has
no
distinctive
interest
as
an
employer
in
sanctioning
such
controversial
but
germane
and
professionally
competent
speech.
321
When
state
officials
take
steps
to
suppress
such
speech,
they
are
doing
so
not
in
their
role
as
employers
but
in their
role
as
regulators.
And
relative
to
the
government
as
regulators,
the
Court
has
emphasized
that
the
First
Amendment
interest
in
developing,
expressing,
and
deliberating
on
controversial
ideas
is
exceedingly
strong.
V.
GOVERNMENT
SPEECH
AND
PRIVATE
SPEECH
IN
STATE
UNIVERSITIES
A
second
possibility
for
upholding
anti-CRT
policies
is
by
characterizing
the
speech
of
professors
in
classrooms
at
state
university
as
a
form
of
government
speech.
The
"Government's
own
speech
...
is
exempt
from
First
Amendment
scrutiny."
3
22
When
the
government
speaks
with
its
own
voice,
it
necessarily
must
make
decisions
based
on
the
content
and
viewpoint
of
the
substantive
issues
on
which
it
chooses
to
speak.
The
government
may
legitimately
favor
some
ideas
and
express
disapproval
of
others
when
the
government
is
engaged
in
its
own
speech.
The
First
Amendment
prevents
the
government
from
suppressing
or
disadvantaging
disfavored
ideas,
but
"it
does
not
regulate
government
speech."
3
23
The
government
can
participate
in
the
marketplace
of
ideas
and
advocate
on
behalf
of
its
own
favored
ideas.
It
just
cannot
dictate
to
the
citizenry
that
it
must
embrace
the
government's
favored
ideas
or
prevent
the
citizenry
from
hearing
competing
perspectives.
It
is
the
very
business
of
government
to
favor
and
disfavor
points
of
view
on
(in
modern
times,
at
least)
innumerable
subjects.
...
And
it
makes
not
a
bit
of
difference,
insofar
as
either
common
sense
or
the
Constitution
is
concerned,
whether
these
officials
further
their
(and,
in
a
democracy,
our)
favored
point
of
view
by
achieving
it
directly
(having
government-
employed
artists
paint
pictures,
for
example,
or
government-
employed
doctors
perform
abortions);
or
by
advocating
it
officially
(establishing
an
Office
of
Art
Appreciation,
for
321.
At
least
this
is
true
given
the
current
mission
of
American
universities
to
preserve,
advance,
and
disseminate
knowledge.
If
the
university
had
a
different
mission,
then
the
state's
interest
as
an
employer
in
suppressing
such
speech
might
likewise
change.
322.
Johanns
v.
Livestock
Mktg.
Ass'n,
544
U.S.
550,
553
(2005).
323.
Pleasant
Grove
City
v.
Summum,
555
U.S.
460,
467
(2009).
513
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
example,
or
an
Office
of
Voluntary
Population
Control);
or by
giving
money
to
others
who
achieve
or
advocate
it
(funding
private
art
classes,
for
example,
or
Planned
Parenthood).
None
of
this
has
anything
to
do
with
abridging
anyone's
speech.
324
The
curriculum
of
a public
school
might readily
be
understood
to
be
an
example
of
such
government
speech.
The
government
creates
the
public
school,
determines
the
curriculum,
chooses
the
textbooks,
and
employs
the
teachers.
When
those
teachers
teach
the
curriculum
in
the
classroom,
they
might
not
be
speaking
for
themselves
but
are
instead
speaking
on
behalf
of
the
government.
325
Teachers
might
be
the
mere
mouthpieces
of
the
government,
and
if
so
then
the
government
necessarily
has the right
to
determine
what
that
mouthpiece
will
say.
When
government
speech
is
at
stake,
the
government
might
give
positive
direction
so
that
certain
ideas
are
expressed
on
its
behalf,
or
it
might
set
negative
limits
so
that
certain
ideas
are
forbidden
to
be
expressed
on
its
behalf.
Even
as
the
Court
recognized
a
First
Amendment
interest
in
resisting
compelled
speech
in
the
flag
salute
case,
it
admitted
that
"the
State
may
'require
teaching
by
instruction
and
study
of
all in
our
history
and
in
the
structure
and
organization
of
our
government,
including
the
guaranties
of
civil
liberty
which
tend
to
inspire
patriotism
and
love
of
country."'
3
2
6
California,
for
example,
not
only
imposes
requirements
regarding
public
school
curriculum,
such
as
the
directive
that
"instruction
in
the
social
sciences
shall
include
.
. .
a
study
of
the
role
and
contributions"
of
myriad
groups
to
the
development
of
the
state
and
the nation
"with
particular
emphasis
on
portraying
the
role
of
these
groups
in
contemporary
society."
327
It
also
prohibits
some
ideas
from
being
included
within
the
public
school
curriculum,
such
as
the
directive
that
no school
board
may
"adopt
any
instructional
materials
for
use
in
the
schools"
that
include
"[a]ny
matter
reflecting
adversely
upon
persons
on
the
basis
of
race
or
ethnicity,
gender,
religion,
disability,
nationality,
or
sexual
orientation"
or
"[a]ny
sectarian
or
denominational
doctrine
or
propaganda
contrary
to law."
328
Through
324.
Nat'l
Endowment
for
the
Arts
v.
Finley,
524
U.S.
569,
598
(1998)
(Scalia,
J., concurring
in
judgment).
325.
See
infra
notes
328-30.
326.
W.
Va.
State
Bd.
of
Educ.
v.
Barnette,
319
U.S.
624,
631
(1943)
(quoting
Minersville
Sch.
Dist.
v.
Gobitis,
310
U.S.
586,
604
(1940)
(Stone,
J.,
dissenting)).
327.
CAL.
EDUC.
CODE
§
51204.5
(West
2012).
The
Texas
anti-CRT
bill
aimed
at
primary
and
secondary
schools
also
included
a
directive
to
the State
Board
of
Education
to
adopt
a
social
studies
curriculum
that
included
specific
topics
and
texts.
H.B.
3979,
87th
Leg.
(Tex.
2021).
The
preexisting
state
code
already
included
substantial
detail
on
what
knowledge
social
studies
in
public
schools
should
cover.
19
TEX.
ADMIN.
CODE
§
113
(2022).
328.
CAL.
EDUC.
CODE
§
60044
(West
2013).
See
also
Steven
Shiffrin,
Government
Speech,
27
UCLA
L.
REv.
565,
568
n.11
(1980).
514
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
the
apparatus
of
the
public
school
system
"the
state
commands
powerful
machinery
to
prescribe
and
to
instill
basic
values
in
politics,
nationalism,
and
other
matters
of
opinion."
329
Giving
the
government
free
rein
to
convey
its
own
messages
nonetheless
creates
some
First
Amendment
complications.
The
state
may
advance
its
"official
view
as
to
proper
appreciation
of
history,
state
pride,
and
individualism,"
for
example,
in any
number
of
ways,
but
it
cannot
dragoon
a
private
individual
into
becoming
"the
courier
for
such
[a]
message."
33
0
Given
the
expansive
scope
of
the
modern
government,
however,
it
is
not
always
obvious
how
to
disentangle
government
speech
from
private
speech.
There
is
a
particular
risk
that
the
government
might
use
the
government-speech
doctrine
"as
a
cover
for
censorship"
331
or
a
"subterfuge
for
favoring
certain
private
speakers
over
others
based
on
viewpoint."
332
It
thus
becomes
particularly
important
to
determine
"whether
the
government
is
actually
expressing
its
own
views
or
the
real
speaker
is
a
private
party
and
the
government
is
surreptitiously
engaged
in
the
'regulation
of
private
speech."'
3
3
3
The
academic-freedom
exception
to
government-employee
speech
explored
in
Part
IV
complicates
an
easy
resolution
of
the
government
speech
problem.
It
is
easier
to
distinguish
between
private
speakers
and
government
speakers
when
considering
speech
by
government
employees
than
when
considering
private
speakers
making
use
of
government
property.
When
a
government
employee
engages
in
speech
pursuant
to
their
official
duties
and
speaks
as
an
employee,
there
is
at
least
a
prima
facie
expectation
that
the
employee
is
speaking
on
behalf
of
the
government.
Government-employee
speech
and
government
speech
are
largely
reconciled
by
Garcetti's
emphasis
on
the
employee's
official
responsibilities,
but
the
academic-freedom
exception
leaves
that
reconciliation
incomplete
in
the
educational
context.
More
work
needs
to
be
done
to
tie
these
threads
together.
The
critical
inquiry
is,
as
Justice
Alito
has
reminded
us,
determining
"whether
the
government
is
speaking
instead
of
regulating
private
expression."
33
4
Professorial
speech
is
recognizably
private
speech
within
the
frameworks
the
Court
has
provided
for
separating
government
speech
from
private
speech.
The
anti-CRT
policies
are
therefore
best
understood
as
efforts
to
regulate
private
expression
rather
than
as
efforts
to
direct
government
speech.
Moreover,
characterizing
professorial
speech
as
private
speech
rather
329.
Shiffrin,
supra
note
328,
at
568.
330.
Wooley
v.
Maynard,
430
U.S.
705,
717
(1977).
331.
Shurtleff
v.
City
of
Boston,
142
S.
Ct.
1583,
1595-96
(2022)
(Alito,
J.,
concurring).
332.
Pleasant
Grove
City
v.
Summum,
555
U.S.
460,
473
(2009).
333.
Shurtleff,
142
S.
Ct.
at
1596
(quoting
Pleasant
Grove
City
v.
Summum,
555
U.S.
460,
467
(2009)).
334.
Id.
at
1595.
515
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
than
government
speech
is
essential
to
realizing
the
aspirations
of
the
academic-freedom
cases
arising
out
of
the
Cold
War.
The
Court
has
not
settled
on
a
single
approach
to
identifying
government
speech.
Justice
Breyer
has
characterized
the
Court's
efforts
in
this
regard
as
one
of
conducting
"a
holistic
inquiry."
335
Justice
Alito
has
characterized
the
Court's
approach
as
"a
fact-bound
totality-of-the-circumstances
inquiry."
33
6
In
canvassing
the
factors
that
the
Court
has
found
relevant
to
marking
out
government
speech,
the
analysis
is
not
unambiguous
but
there
are
good
reasons
for
thinking
that
professorial
speech
is
best
considered
to
be
private
expression.
In
some
recent
cases,
the
Court
has
emphasized
three
main
factors
in
identifying
government
speech:
whether
the
history
of
the
medium
of
expression
"long
[has]
communicated
messages
from
the"
government,
337
whether
the
medium
is
"often
closely
identified
in
the
public
mind
with
the
government,"
33 8
and
whether
the
government
maintains
"direct
control
over
the
messages
conveyed"
through
the
medium.
339
These
factors
cut
against
treating
professorial
speech
at
state
universities
as
a
form of
government
speech.
34
0
State
universities
are
agencies
of
the
state
and
professors
at
those
universities
are
government
employees,
but
state
universities
have
not
generally
been
understood
as
vehicles
for
communicating
messages
from
the
government.
State
universities
have
instead
generally
been
understood
to
be
peculiar
institutions
within
the
state
government
that
operate
with
a
high
degree
of
autonomy
from
state
political
leaders.
The
state
maintains
oversight,
generally
through
a
politically
appointed
board
of
regents,
but
does
not
attempt
to
direct
its
institutions
of
higher
education.
State
officials
do
not
specify
the
textbooks
or
detail
the
curriculum
to
be
taught
in
universities.
If
state-university
professors
were
engaged
in
government
speech
when
in
the
classroom,
then
we
would
expect
government
officials
to
comprehensively
direct
what
it
is
that
professors
say.
Instead,
state
officials
have
contented
themselves
to
intervene
only
to
prohibit
the
discussion
of
certain
ideas
in
the
classroom,
which
looks
far
less
like
335.
Id.
at
1589.
336.
Id.
at
1596.
337.
Walker
v.
Tex.
Div.,
Sons
of
Confederate
Veterans,
Inc.,
576
U.S.
200,
211
(2015).
See
also
Summum,
555
U.S.
at
470;
Shurtleff,
142
S.
Ct.
at
1590.
338.
Summum,
555
U.S.
at
472.
See
also
Walker,
576
U.S.
at
212;
Shurtleff,
142
S.
Ct.
at
1591.
339.
Walker,
576
U.S.
at
213.
See
also
Summum,
555
U.S.
at
470;
Shurtleff,
142
S.
Ct.
at
1592.
340.
In
evaluating
whether
a
high
school
football
coach's
prayer
was
government
speech,
the
Court
largely
relied
on
the
government-employee
speech
cases
to
determine
whether
the
prayer
was
delivered
pursuant
to
the
coach's
duties
as
a
government
employee.
Kennedy
v.
Bremerton
Sch.
Dist.,
142
S.
Ct.
2407,
2423-25
(2022).
As
outlined
in
Part
IV,
that
analysis
would
be
inadequate
for
thinking
about
the
particular
circumstances
of
professorial
speech.
516
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
using
classroom
lectures
as
vehicles
for
communicating
messages
from
the
government
and
far
more
like
the
government
censoring
ideas
that
it
does
not
like.
Some
state
constitutions
enshrine
an
element
of
independence
for
their
universities.
The
California
Constitution
of
1879,
for
example,
specifies
that
the
University
of
California
"shall
constitute
a
public
trust
..
.
subject
only
to
such
legislative
control
as
may
be
necessary
to
insure
.
. .
compliance
with
the
terms
of
the
endowments."
341
The
University
of
California
was
to
be
"entirely
independent
of
all
political
or
sectarian
influence."
3
42
The
launch
of
some
state
universities
emphasized
their
political
independence.
The
great
education
reformer
James
Angell
began
his
term
as
president
of
the
University
of
Michigan
in
1871
by
emphasizing
that
"the
University
cannot
do
its
work
with
the
highest
success
unless
it
have
[sic]
a
certain
degree
of
independence
and
self-control."
3
43
The
university
should
be
"catholic
and
unsectarian,"
3
4
4
and
the
faculty
should
never
be
required
to
mouth
"the
shibboleths
of
sect
or
party."
34
5
Andrew
Sloan
Draper
took
the
reins
of
the
University
of
Illinois
by
declaring
that
public
universities
"must
exhibit
catholicity
of
spirit;
it
must
tolerate
all
creeds;
it
must
inspire
all
schools."
3
46
Andrew
Dickson
White
at
Cornell
proclaimed,
"[N]o
professor,
officer
or
student
shall
ever
be
accepted
or
rejected
on
account
of
any
religious
or
political
views
which
he
may
or
may
not
hold."
34
7
State
universities
have
historically
been
held
out
as
independent
institutions
that
were
explicitly
not
represented
as
conduits
for
government
speech.
State
universities
were
created
to
advance
a
public
purpose
but
not
to
express
a
governmental
message.
They
were
understood
to
be
useful
for
training
well-educated
citizens
and
for
generating
useful
knowledge
in
the
arts
and
sciences.
Charles
Van
Hise
at
the
University
of
Wisconsin
voiced
the
aspiration
of
many
in
declaring,
"The
practical
man
of
all
practical
men
is
he
who,
with
his
face
toward
truth,
follows
wherever
it
may
lead."
3
48
It
was
hoped
that
the
unleashing
of
that
scholarly
spirit
to
follow
the
truth
wherever
it
might
lead
would
allow
the
university
and
its
faculty
"to
be
benefactors,
not
only
of
the
state,
but
of
the
entire
earth;
for
a
new
truth,
a
new
principle,
is
not
the
property
of
any
state,
but
instantly
belongs
to
the
world."
34
9
State
universities
could
only
accomplish
341.
CAL.
CONST.
art.
IX,
§
9
(1879).
342.
Id.
343.
JAMES
BURRILL
ANGELL,
SELECTED
ADDRESSES
30
(1912).
344.
Id.
at
29.
345.
Id.
at
31.
346.
ANDREW
S.
DRAPER,
AMERICAN
EDUCATION
197
(1909).
347.
THE
CORNELL
UNIVERSITY
REGISTER,
1869-70
21
(1870).
348.
THE
JUBILEE
OF
THE
UNIVERSITY
OF
WISCONSIN
123
(1905).
349.
Id.
517
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
their
purpose
if
they
were
not
restricted
to
repeating
popular
orthodoxies
and
if
they
were
insulated
from
the
expectation
of
being
a
mere
mouthpiece
of
incumbent
politicians.
There
is
no
question
that
state
universities
are
associated
in
the
public
mind
with
the
state
itself,
but
it
seems
much
more
dubious
that
the
public
identifies
professorial
speech
with
the
state
government.
Indeed,
a
common
complaint
about
state
universities
and
state-
university
professors
is
how
divorced
they
are
from
the
attitudes
and
perspectives
of
the
ordinary
citizens
of
the
state.
Unlike
a
monument
on
public
land
or
a
slogan
emblazoned
on
a
"government
ID,"350
professorial
speech
is
not
a
static
message
presumptively
endorsed
by
a
government.
Professors
are
far
more
likely
to
be
seen
as
individuals,
or
as
part
of
a
distinctive
professorial
class,
than
as
avatars
of
the
governments
that
happen
to
employ
them.
When
conservatives
complain
about
"tenured
radicals"
351
or
populists
complain
about
"pointy-headed
intellectuals,"
3
5
2
they
are
emphasizing
the
gap
between
the
professoriate
and
the
government
and
community
they
serve.
Professorial
speech
is
not
"effectively
controlled"
by
the
government.
35
3
What
an
individual
professor
might
say
in
the
classroom
or
in
his
or
her
scholarly
research
certainly
is
not
"set
out
.
..
from
beginning
to
end"
by
the
government.
35 4
Professorial
speech
is
not
"selected"
by
the
government
"for
the
purpose
of
presenting
the
image
of
the
[government]
that
it
wishes
to
project
to
all"
who
might
hear
it.355
Professors
themselves
are
not
even
directly
selected
by
"government
decisionmakers"
in
any
traditional
sense
but
are
rather
selected
by
their
faculty
peers
to
occupy
their
positions.
356
Although
content-based
judgments
are
made
to
assess
the
quality
of
their
work,
they
are
not
the
kind
of
content-based
factors
that
are
designed
to
align
professorial
speech
with
governmental
preferences.
Scholars
are
chosen
to
advance
knowledge
within
their
discipline
and
not
to
rehearse
"the
shibboleths
of
sect
or
party."
35
7
Once
professors
are
appointed
to
their
positions,
government
officials
do
not
"exercise
editorial
control"
over
the
content
of
their
classroom
or
scholarly
speech.
3
58
To
the
extent
that
there
are
gatekeepers
to
the
publication
of
scholarly
research,
it
is
a
network
of
scholarly
peers
hailing
from
350.
Walker
v.
Tex.
Div.,
Sons
of
Confederate
Veterans,
Inc.,
576
U.S.
200,
212
(2015).
351.
ROGER
KIMBALL,
TENURED
RADICALS
(1990).
352.
Norman
C.
Miller,
A
Place
in
the
Sun:
George
Wallace
Faces
Crucial
Test
in
Florida
-
On
Favorable
Ground,
WALL
ST.
J.,
Feb.
9,
1972,
at
1.
353.
Johanns
v.
Livestock
Mktg.
Ass'n,
544
U.S.
550,
560
(2005).
354.
Id.
355.
Pleasant
Grove
City
v.
Summum,
555
U.S.
460,
473
(2009).
356.
Id.
at
472.
357.
ANGELL,
supra
note
343,
at
31.
358.
Summum,
555
U.S.
at
472.
518
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
across
the
country
and
the
globe
and
who
likely
have
no
connection
whatsoever
to
the
state
government
that
might
employ
the
author
of
the
work.
In
appointing
professors
to
the
faculty
of
state
universities,
even
university
officials
largely
cede
control
over
the
content
of
professorial
speech
to
the
individual
professor
and
to
the
larger
scholarly
community.
In
short,
professorial
speech
in
state
universities
shows
none
of
the
expected
characteristics
of
government
speech.
Classroom
lectures
in
state
universities
have
not
traditionally
been
understood
to
communicate
messages
from
the
government.
University
professors
are
not
associated
in
the
public
mind
with
the
government.
The
government
does
not
exercise
direct
control
over
the
content
of
classroom
lectures.
This
is
not
a
situation
in
which
"the
government
established
the
message;
maintained
control
of
its
content;
and
controlled
its
dissemination
to
the
public."
35 9
Professorial
speech
likewise
does
not
meet
the
looser
analysis
favored
by
Justice
Alito
for
identifying
government
speech.
The
government
exercises
even
less
control
over
professorial
speech
than
it
does
over
trademark
registration,
for
example.
There
is
no
examiner
of
professorial
speech
who
is
attempting
to
"inquire
whether
any
viewpoint
conveyed
by
[that
speech]
is
consistent
with
Government
policy
or
whether
any
such
viewpoint
is
consistent
with
that
expressed
by
other"
professors
employed
at
the
university.
36
0
Given
the
diversity
of
scholarly
views
of
professors,
if
professorial
speech
is
government
speech,
then
the
government
"is
babbling
prodigiously
and
incoherently."
36
1
Justice
Alito's
thought
experiment
in
the
specialty
license
plate
case
asked
whether
a
reasonable
observer
could
see
myriad
college
football
teams
promoted
on
specialty
license
plates
and
"assume
that
the
State
of
Texas
was
officially
(and
perhaps
treasonously)
rooting
for
the
Longhorns'
opponents?"
3
6
2
Justice
Alito
has
identified
what
he
considers
"the
minimum
conditions"
for
identifying
speech
as
government
speech
and
that
is
that
the
"government
purposefully
expresses
a
message
of
its
own
through
persons
authorized
to
speak
on
its
behalf,
and
in
doing
so,
does
not
rely
on
a
means
that
abridges
private
speech."
3
63
"Government
speech
is
thus
the
purposeful
communication
of
a
governmentally
determined
message
by
a
person
exercising
a
power
to
speak
for
a
government."
36
4
But
no
one
thinks
that
a
state-
359.
Page
v.
Lexington
Cnty.
Sch.
Dist.
One,
531
F.3d
275,
282
(4th
Cir.
2008).
360.
Matal
v.
Tam,
137
S.
Ct.
1744,
1758
(2017).
361.
Id.
362.
Walker
v.
Tex.
Div.,
Sons
of
Confederate
Veterans,
Inc.,
576
U.S.
200,
222
(2015).
363.
Shurtleff
v.
City
of
Boston,
142
S.
Ct.
1583,
1598
(2022)
(Alito,
J.,
concurring).
364.
Id.
519
2023]
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
university
professor
is
"a
person
with
the
power
to
determine
what
messages
the
government
will
communicate."
365
To
take
but
a
single
example,
nobody
believes
that
when
Sandy
Levinson,
the
W.
St.
John
Garwood
and
W.
St.
John
Garwood,
Jr.
Centennial
Professor
at
the
University
of
Texas
School
of
Law,
deigns
to
speak
in
class
about
Marbury
v.
Madison,
3
66
that
his
views
on
that
case
are
shared
even
by
other
members
of
the
law
school
faculty
or
the
Garwood
family,
let
alone
by
Governor
Greg
Abbott
or
Attorney
General
Ken
Paxton.
36
7
Levinson
is
neither
authorized
to
nor
understood
to
be
communicating
"a
governmentally
determined
message"
when
speaking
in
class
at
a
state
university.
36
8
He
is
employed
to
provide
his
idiosyncratic
scholarly
expertise,
not
to
be
a
spokesman
for
the
state
of
Texas.
His
classroom
speech
does
not
"amount
to
government
speech
attributable"
to
the
Texas
government.
3
69
Recognizing
that
a
professor's
speech
in
a
classroom
"represent[s]
his
own
private
speech"
37 0
and
not
government
speech
is
ultimately
necessary
to
preserving
the
logic
and
goals
of
the
Court's
academic-
freedom
jurisprudence.
The
stated
purpose
of
protecting
academic
freedom
under
the
First
Amendment
is
to
prevent
"laws
that
cast
a
pall
of
orthodoxy
over
the
classroom."
37
1
If
classroom
speech
is
best
understood
as
government
speech,
then
the
entire
point
would
be
to
impose
orthodoxy.
Students
might
not
have
to
accept
that
orthodoxy
as
true,
but
professors
would
be
obliged
to
convey
it.
If
professors
are
paid
strictly
to
toe
the
company
line
when
speaking
to
students,
it
would
have
"an
unmistakable
tendency
to
chill
that
free
play
of
the
spirit
which
all
teachers
ought
especially
to
cultivate
and
practice."
372
The
academic-freedom
cases
defend
the
possibility
that
professors
in
their
classrooms
will
dissent
from
the
government's
own
policies,
principles,
and
values.
Indeed,
at
the
heart
of
the
academic-freedom
cases
was
whether
professors
could
advocate
that
the
US
government
itself
be
dissolved.
There
is
no
sense
in
which
Paul
Sweezy's
lecture
to
the
students
in
a
class
at
the
University
of
New
Hampshire
could
be
regarded
as
government
speech.
For
the
Court
to
uphold
the
right
of
Sweezy
and
others
like
him
to
teach
the
truth
as
he
understood
it
in
state-university
classrooms,
that
speech
had
to
be
understood
as
private
speech
subject
to
First
Amendment
protection.
And
it
had
to
365.
Id.
366.
1
Cranch
137
(1803);
see
Sanford
Levinson
&
Jack
M.
Balkin,
What
Are
the
Facts
of
Marbury
v.
Madison?,
20
CONST.
COMMENT.
255
(2003).
367.
On
Levinson's
reluctance
to
teach
Marbury,
see
Sanford
Levinson,
Why
I
Do
Not
Teach
Marbury
(Except
to
Eastern
Europeans)
and
Why
You
Shouldn't
Either,
38
WAKE
FOREST
L.
REV.
553
(2003).
368.
Shurtleff,
142
S.
Ct.
at
1598.
369.
Kennedy
v.
Bremerton
Sch.
Dist.,
142
S.
Ct.
2407,
2424
(2022).
370.
Id.
at
2425.
371.
Keyishian
v.
Bd.
of
Regents,
385
U.S.
589,
603
(1967).
372.
Wieman
v.
Updegraff,
344
U.S.
183,
195
(1952).
520
[Vol.
58
2023]
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
521
be
understood
as
private
speech
subject
to
First
Amendment
protection
even
when
expressed
by
a
state-university
professor
acting
pursuant
to
his
official
duties
as
an
instructor
in
a
classroom.
That
is
not
to
say
that
there
may
be
no
government
speech
on
state-university
campuses.
37
3
The
government
might
require,
for
example,
that
an
official
governmental
statement
be
included
in
course
syllabi
or
distributed
to
university
students,
comparable
to
the
"ministerial"
speech
that
university
officials
sometimes
require
of
faculty.
374
The
government
might
specially
authorize
particular
programming
or
even
particular
classes
and
course
materials
in
which
professors
might
choose
to
participate.
In
that
way,
government
officials
might
supplement
the
regular
academic
offerings
of
the
university
and
exercise
greater
editorial
control
over
that
specific
subset
of
academic
activities
in
a
manner
that
made
it
clear
that
that
the
course
content
was
in
fact
government
speech.
375
373.
I
set
aside
the
question
of
the
implications
for
academic
freedom
for
professorial
speech
if
a
state
were
to
resolve
to
comprehensively
direct
the
university
curriculum
as
it
does
the
primary
and
secondary
school
curriculum.
No
state
has
sought
to
treat
higher
education
as
it
does
secondary
education,
or
to
say
of
a
university
board
of
trustees
what
can be
said
of
a
local
school
board,
that
"[o]nly
the
school
board
has
ultimate
responsibility
for
what
goes
on
the
classroom,
legitimately
giving
it
a
say
over
what
teachers
may
(or
may
not)
teach
in
the
classroom."
Evans-Marshall
v.
Bd.
of
Educ.,
624
F.3d
332,
340
(6th
Cir.
2010).
Whether
the
First
Amendment
creates
an
impassable
obstacle
to
a
state
attempting
to
exercise
such
control
over
a
university
is
a
distinguishable
question
from
whether
a
state
can
attempt
to
impose
discrete
constraints
on
professorial
speech
given
the
kinds
of
universities
that
they
have
established.
For
skepticism
that
even
primary
and
secondary
schools
should
be
understood
as
pure
instruments
of
government
speech,
see
MARK
G.
YUDOF,
WHEN
GOVERNMENT
SPEAKS
215-18
(1983).
374.
Meriwether
v.
Hartop,
992
F.3d
492,
507
(6th
Cir.
2021).
It
is
not
obvious
that
ministerial
speech
must
also
be
"non-ideological"
in
order
to
be
consistent
with
First
Amendment
protections
for
academic
freedom.
A
professor
cannot
be
compelled
to
endorse
ideological
statements
or
express
them
as
her
own
without
running
afoul
of
the
protections
outlined
in
Barnette.
W.
Va.
State
Bd.
of
Educ.
v.
Barnette,
319
U.S.
624
(1943).
But
if,
for
example,
a
state
university
required
a
professor
to
convey
the
state's
own
ideologically
freighted
message
in
a
manner
that
made
clear
that
the
message
came
from
the
state
and
not
from
the
professor,
then
it
is
not
apparent
that
the
professor's
First
Amendment
rights
have
been
infringed.
Even
if
it
is
permissible
for
a
university
to
require
a
professor
to
include
the
government's
message
in
the
form
of
a
specified
land
acknowledgement
or
diversity
statement
in
a
course
syllabus,
it
is
surely
not
permissible
for
a
university
to
compel
a
professor
to
present
such
a
message
as
if
it
were
the
professor's
own
or
to
refrain
from
supplementing
the
government's
message
with
an
alternative
viewpoint
on
that
topic.
On
the
value
of
a
transparency
requirement
for
government
speech,
see
HELEN
NORTON,
THE
GOVERNMENT'S
SPEECH
AND
THE
CONSTITUTION
43-49
(2019).
375.
Such
an
academic
unit
might
be
modeled
on
pontifical
faculty
accredited
by
the
Holy
See
at
the
Catholic
University
of
America.
Professors
in
the
school
of
theology
are
expected
to
adhere
to
Church
teachings,
but
professors
in
the
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
In
short,
the
government
might,
consistent
with
academic
freedom,
add
government
speech
to
the
intellectual
life
of
a
state
university,
so
long
as
it
does
so
in
a
manner
that
does
not
restrain
or
crowd
out
the
freedom
of
members
of
the
faculty
to
express
countervailing
ideas
in
the
course
of
their
teaching
and
scholarship.
It
cannot,
however,
displace
private
professorial
speech
with
government
speech
or
use
government
speech
as
a
cover
for
censoring
private
professorial
speech.
376
To
borrow
from
a
different
line
of
First
Amendment
doctrine,
in
adding
government
speech
to
a
university
environment,
the
state
must
"leave
open
ample
alternative
channels"
for
communicating
the
private
professorial
speech
protected
by
academic
freedom.
377
CONCLUSION
Relative
to
both
government-employee
speech
doctrine
and
government-speech
doctrine,
"academic
freedom
is
.
. .
a
special
subset
of
First
Amendment
freedoms,"
as
William
Van
Alstyne
once
argued.
378
If
academic
freedom-specifically
the
freedom
of
state-
university
professors
to
teach
and
to
engage
in
scholarship
without
interference
from
government
officials-is
worth
protecting,
and
the
Supreme
Court
has
held
that
it
is,
379
then
it
cannot
be
subsumed
under
common
categories
of
speech
within
First
Amendment
jurisprudence.
The
fact
that
professors
express
views
that
the
politicians
dislike
in
the
classroom
and
in
their
scholarship
does
not
put
them
outside
the
reach
of
the
First
Amendment.
Professorial
speech
has
limits
and
exceeding
those
limits
can
properly
result
in
a
professor
being
sanctioned
for
something
that
he
or
she
has
said,
but
those
limits
are
not
determined
by
whether
politicians
find
the
ideas
expressed
to
be
offensive,
disturbing,
or even
dangerous.
The
anti-CRT
policies,
such
as
Florida's
Stop
WOKE
Act,
prohibit
university
instruction
that
"espouses,
promotes
[or]
advances"
department
of
philosophy
enjoy
the
usual
degree
of
academic
freedom
to
depart
from
Church
teachings.
1
THE
CATHOLIC
UNIVERSITY
OF
AMERICA
FACULTY
HANDBOOK
15
(2017),
https://pohcies.catholic.edu/_media/docs/facultyhandbooki_2018.pdf.
376.
See
also Shurtleff
v.
City
of
Boston,
142
S.
Ct.
1583,
1599
(2022)
("So
government
speech
in
the
literal
sense
is
not
exempt
from
First
Amendment
attack
if
it
uses
a
means
that
restricts
private
expression
in
a
way
that
'abridges'
the
freedom
of
speech,
as
is
the
case
with
compelled
speech.
Were
it
otherwise,
virtually
every
government
action
that
regulates
private
speech
would,
paradoxically,
qualify
as
government
speech
unregulated
by
the
First
Amendment.
Naked
censorship
of
a
speaker
based
on
viewpoint,
for
example,
might
well
constitute
'expression'
in
the
thin
sense
that
it
conveys
the
government's
disapproval
of
the
speaker's
message.
But
plainly
that
kind
of
action
cannot
fall
beyond
the
reach
of
the
First
Amendment.").
377.
Clark
v.
Cmty.
for
Creative
Non-Violence,
468
U.S.
288,
293
(1984).
378.
Van
Alstyne,
supra
note
15,
at
143.
379.
Keyishian
v.
Bd.
of
Regents,
385
U.S.
589, 603
(1967).
522
[Vol.
58
CLASSROOM
DISCUSSIONS
specific
concepts.
38
0
The
policies
denounce
the
idea
that
a
person
is
privileged
in
American
society
due
to
his
race
or
sex
or
that
a
person
should
receive
adverse
treatment
because
of
past
actions
by
members
of
his
race.
3
81
The
state
might
believe
that
such
ideas
are
wrongheaded,
but
espousing
them
is
common
in
contemporary
political
and
scholarly
debates.
Such
policies
allow
professors
to
present
one
side
of
debates
over
affirmative
action,
for
example,
but
forbid
them
from
advancing
the
other
side.
If
state
universities
are
to
remain
institutions
of
higher
learning
in
which
controversial
ideas
can
be
explored,
contested,
and
examined,
government
officials
cannot
exclude
some
viewpoints
as
heretical.
The
current
wave
of
anti-CRT
policies
could
pose
the
biggest
threat
of
governmental
interference
with
academic
freedom
in
American
universities
since
the
McCarthy
era.
Fortunately,
the
Court
developed
a
forceful
commitment
to
recognizing
academic
freedom
as
being
protected
by
the
First
Amendment
as
a
result
of
that
earlier
wave
of
legislative
interventions
into
the
intellectual
life
of
universities.
Unfortunately,
the
Court
has
not
clarified
the
scope
of
this
academic-freedom
principle
under
the
First
Amendment,
nor
has
it
reconciled
that
earlier
jurisprudence
with
later
case
law
relating
to
government-employee
speech
and
government
speech.
The
courts
will
be
forced
to
grapple
with
how
these
various
strands
of
doctrine
should
be
woven
together.
It
is
possible
to
weave
them
together,
but
doing
so
reveals
the
constitutional
infirmities
of
common
anti-CRT
proposals
being
advanced
in
the
states.
The
Supreme
Court
has
invited
confusion
by
noting
but
not
fleshing
out
an
academic-freedom
exception
to
ordinary
government-
employee
speech
doctrine.
It
is
possible
to
flesh
out
that
exception
in
a
way
that
coheres
with
the
Court's
various
doctrinal
commitments,
but
it
will
require
reaffirming
that
professorial
speech
is
"a
special
concern
of
the
First
Amendment."
3
82
When
state
government
officials
attempt
to
restrict
what
ideas
can
be
taught
in
the
classrooms
of
public
universities,
they
do
real
damage
not
only
to
the
intellectual
life
of
those
universities
but
also
to
the
public
discourse
of
the
country.
The
First
Amendment
is
grounded
in
the
fundamental
commitment
to
the
view
that
ideas
should
be
freely
discussed
and
that
they
cannot
be
rejected
or
embraced
as
a
result
of
government
diktat.
In
the
mid-
twentieth
century,
the
government
sought
to
prevent
the
spread
on
college
campuses
of
what
it
regarded
as
dangerous
ideas
by
dismissing
any
professor
who
might
adhere
to
them,
discuss
them,
or
teach
them.
The
Court
rejected
the
stifling
hand
of
censorship
then.
The
tools
of
censorship
being
wielded
by
the
government
today
are
different,
but
the
ultimate
goal
is
the
same.
Government
officials
do
380.
FLA.
STAT.
§
1000.05
(2021).
381.
FLA.
STAT.
§
760.10(8)(a)(5)
(2022).
382.
Keyishian,
385
U.S.
at
603.
523
2023]
524
WAKE
FOREST
LAW
REVIEW
[Vol.
58
not
want
professors
at
state
universities
to
discuss
ideas
with
which
those
government
officials,
and
perhaps
even
popular
democratic
majorities,
disagree.
The
First
Amendment
bars
them
from
having
their
way.