Authors: Ole F. Norheim, Joelle M. Abi-Rached, Liam Kofi Bright, Kristine Bærøe, Octávio L.M. Ferraz,
Siri Gloppen, Alex Voorhoeve
Difficult trade-offs in response to
COVID-19: the case for open and
inclusive decision-making
Authors
1
and aliations
Ole F. Norheim
2
Bergen Centre for Ethics and Priority Setting, Department of Global Public Health and Primary Care, University of Bergen,
Bergen, Norway
Department of Global Health and Population, Harvard T.H. Chan School of Public Health, Boston (MA), USA
Joelle M. Abi-Rached
École Normale Supérieure and Médialab, Sciences Po, Paris, France
Liam Kofi Bright
Department of Philosophy, Logic and Scientic Method, London School of Economics, London, United Kingdom
Kristine Bærøe
Bergen Centre for Ethics and Priority Setting, Department of Global Public Health and Primary Care, University of Bergen,
Bergen, Norway
Octávio L.M. Ferraz
Transnational Law Institute, The Dickson Poon School of Law, King’s College London, London, United Kingdom
Siri Gloppen
Centre on Law and Social Transformation, Department of Comparative Politics, University of Bergen, Bergen, Norway
Alex Voorhoeve
Department of Philosophy, Logic and Scientic Method, London School of Economics, London, United Kingdom
Departments of Applied Economics and Philosophy, Erasmus University, Rotterdam, Netherlands
1
A shorter version of this article is [submitted/in print] as a Comment to Nature Medicine
2
Corresponding author: Ole F. Norheim. Bergen Centre for Ethics and Priority Setting, Department of Global Public Health and Primary Care, University of Bergen, Bergen, Norway.
Address: Årstadveien 21, 5020 Bergen, Norway. E-mail: [email protected]
Difficult trade-offs in response to
COVID-19: the case for open and
inclusive decision-making
Cover photo: © 2020 David Pereiras
iii
Contents
Contents
Introduction .......................................................................... 1
What is at stake ........................................................................ 2
Participation as a human right ........................................................... 5
Elements of open and inclusive decision-making............................................ 7
The case for fair processes ............................................................ 7
The role of experts ................................................................... 9
Challenges for vulnerable countries ...................................................... 10
Experiences of participatory processes in the context of COVID-19 ........................... 12
Concluding remarks ................................................................... 15
References ........................................................................... 19
1
Introduction
The COVID-19 pandemic has forced governments
to make dicult choices that profoundly aect
their populations’ health, wealth and liberties. In
order to address the public health and economic
emergencies generated by the pandemic, these
high-stakes decisions have often been made
quickly, with little involvement of stakeholders
in deliberations about which policies to pursue.
Even in emergencies, however, there are important
practical, moral and legal reasons for open, inclusive
decision-making. This improves the quality of
decisions, increases their legitimacy, engenders
Introduction
trust and generates greater conformity with public
health and social measures. Such deliberations
also show respect for peoples ability to offer,
assess and act on reasons and are required by the
principles of human rights and rule of law. When
hard policy choices and trade-os are required
regularly, the processes must be institutionalized,
so that broad-based, transparent decision-making
becomes a routine, central feature of governance.
We characterize such decision-making, argue the
case for it and oer examples of how to put it
intopractice.
Dicult trade-os in response to COVID-19: the case for open and inclusive decision-making
2
Despite considerable uncertainty about the health
impacts of SARS-CoV-2, the scientic consensus
is that the burden on health of its uncontrolled
spread would be substantial (1). In the absence of
policies to slow its spread, it is likely that more than
50% of the population of each country would be
infected (2). Estimates of the infection fatality rate
depend on each countrys characteristics, including
demography, but are 0.23–1.15% (3), suggesting
that the direct eect of uncontrolled spread of
COVID-19 would be the deaths of at least 0.1–0.6%
of aected countries population, concentrated
among the elderly, and among vulnerable, socio-
economically disadvantaged and marginalized
groups (4–6). Moreover, for many people, non-fatal
infections may result in signicant health eects
(so-called “long COVID”), and the burden of caring
for patients with COVID-19 could overwhelm
health systems.
To limit COVID-19-related morbidity and mortality,
many governments have expanded the capacity
of their health care systems and invested in the
development and provision of treatments and
vaccines. They have also turned to a range of
public health and social measures, including:
public health messaging (such as advice on
how to prevent acquiring and transmitting
SARS-CoV-2), sometimes accompanied
by efforts to counter misinformation and
contrary opinions;
personal protective measures (such as hand-
washing and mask-wearing);
environmental measures (such as cleaning,
use of screens and ventilation);
surveillance and response measures
(including testing, contact-tracing, mandating
isolation of those with the disease, those
exposed and travellers from high-risk areas);
and
What is at stake
physical distancing measures, from requiring
space in workplaces and shops to imposing
limits on all non-essential social contact,
often referred to as lockdowns”.
In accordance with our brief, we focus on such
measures. Even if new vaccines are approved, full
vaccine coverage will take time, and public health
and social measures will be necessary for the
foreseeable future. Each measure can be applied
to dierent degrees. The stringency of a lockdown
can vary in several dimensions:
severity: the degree and extent of contact
limitation, from a requirement to stay at
home except for work, education or shopping
for essentials to a complete ban on leaving
home;
selectivity: who is subject to the limitations,
from people living in areas with a high
prevalence to the whole country and from
particular social groups, such as older or
extremely vulnerable people, to the entire
population;
start date: the extent of spread of the virus in
a given population at the time the lockdown
is imposed;
duration: how long the restrictions are
imposed;
aim: to control the spread of the virus so
that the prevalence is kept at a level that the
health system can manage, or to suppress it
completely so that it is almost fully eliminated;
and
enforcement: the eectiveness with which
restrictions are enforced, through state power
and social norms.
3
What is at stake
Such policies have complex effects. Modelling
suggests and country experience demonstrates
that, if these public health and social measures
are deployed effectively and early enough in
the pandemic, they can very eectively limit the
spread of the virus and thereby greatly attenuate
its direct impacts on health (7–10). Many of these
measures, however, also have substantial costs.
Environmental measures to reduce infectiousness
are burdensome. Mandatory isolation is a
substantial limitation on freedom of movement
and association, and contact-tracing infringes on
peoples privacy and generates concern about
concentrating personal data in government
agencies and large technology companies (11).
Lockdowns also severely limit peoples freedom
of movement and association, as well as their
freedom to protest. They also have substantial
short-term economic costs. Countries that imposed
stringent lockdowns had sharper falls in gross
domestic product per capita in the rst half of
2020 compared to pre-pandemic projections, and
the eect persists after correction for the severity
of the pandemic in each country (12). The scale of
economic contraction in countries that have had
stringent lockdowns varies but is substantial: from
about 4% of gross domestic product in Ireland
to 16% in India and more than 20% in Peru (12).
In high-income countries, more than half of the
fall might have been due to the stringency of the
lockdowns (8,9). Moreover, stringent lockdowns
also dissuade people from seeking the health
care and preventive interventions they need and
have exacerbated mental health problems, the
risk of suicide, domestic violence, addiction and
loneliness (13). They have also aected child care,
education and therefore the ability of parents
towork.
People who are socio-economically worse off
or otherwise marginalized have most at stake.
Those who are much poorer than others are at
higher risk of becoming infected because of their
poor working and living conditions (14). They also
disproportionately suer the negative eects of
a lockdown, unless it is accompanied by targeted
economic support. For example, people who rely on
the informal economy (including disproportionate
numbers of poor and marginalized groups,
such as indigenous peoples (15), migrant and
undocumented workers, internally displaced
people and refugees) often live in dire, crowded
conditions, are badly aected by restrictions on
economic activity and movement and often have
less access to social safety nets or health care
(16). For these groups, stringent lockdowns and
the associated economic downturn may impose
severe, possibly life-threatening limitations on
their access to basic necessities (17,18). Other
eects are also concentrated in disadvantaged
groups. When lockdowns limit access to child care,
they aect womens access to work (12). When they
limit in-person education, they delay learning,
and this appears to be concentrated among the
poorestgroups (19).
The policy space that countries have to address
health and economic crises varies. Well-off
countries with well-functioning governments and
high borrowing capacity have a wider spectrum
of possible policy interventions than less wealthy
countries and countries with diminished State
capacity. Emerging economies and middle-income
countries that depend heavily on exports, foreign
remittances, tourism or capital inows will be the
hardest hit by a global economic downturn and
may nd that their borrowing capacity (and hence
their capacity to oset the economic impact of
lockdowns) is constrained (20). In addition, some
poor and developing countries were already
experiencing crises, including war, economic crisis
and/or a breakdown in governance (21).
All countries therefore face a difficult task in
balancing the uncertain and unequal impacts
of public health and social measures on health,
income, liberty, education and other goods.
In making such decisions, there is reason to
believe that the degree of trust in government
and consensus on public measures substantially
influence which policies are feasible and the
balance of benets and burdens of those policies.
Lockdowns and their public health and social
measures are probably less costly if they are
implemented before the virus has spread widely
(see, e.g. 22). Early action, before the eects of the
virus on health are evident, requires condence
of the population in the state. Willingness to
adhere to policies when there is a lot at stake for
individuals and information about the threat is
Dicult trade-os in response to COVID-19: the case for open and inclusive decision-making
4
both uncertain and complex requires trust in those
who make decisions. If there is trust, adherence is
likely to be more widespread, as people will more
often be voluntarily motivated to act in accordance
with the policies. Policies are more effective
when compliance is greater, and, as noted above,
compliance may depend on the extent to which
the public trusts the government’s eectiveness
and its handling of personal data and it has the
assurance that other members of the public are
complying.
Although it is clear that lockdowns have substantial,
identified, immediate economic and social
effects, those saved by lockdowns are less well
identified, and the potential economic benefits
of reduced transmission are far in the future and
less certain. The health gains are also insecure,
unless the lockdown can be sustained until the
virus is adequately suppressed. Lockdown policies
are therefore a “bargain into which the public can
be expected to enter only if they have sucient
condence that they will be eective.
Public agreement to measures that restrict
peoples liberty crucially determines the severity
of the burdens imposed by those restrictions.
While lockdowns and associated measures limit
freedom, they are imposed for a purpose long
recognized by defenders of individual rights:
the prevention of harm to others, in this case by
preventing transmission of a dangerous virus
(23). Although such restrictions may infringe on
individuals’ rights to free movement, association,
public protest and religious worship, when
deliberation leads to widespread acceptance, there
will be fewer challenges to measures that restrict
liberty. Moreover, restrictions are less invasive of
the autonomy of those who accept them, as they
can still live by principles they accept. Acceptance
will increase voluntary adherence and thus limit
the need for coercive measures. In line with this
reasoning, research suggests that condence in
state institutions is an important factor in reducing
the health burden of COVID-19 (14).
In this article, we argue that transparent, inclusive
decision-making contributes to public condence
and policy adherence. We present the broader
normative case for giving a say to all those whose
health, wealth and liberties are at stake, which, in
a pandemic, is all of a countrys inhabitants.
5
Participation as a human right
Transparent, inclusive, accountable decision-
making is required by the principles of human
rights and of the rule of law to which most countries
are committed through their participation in
international treaties and the provisions of their
domestic laws, including constitutions. The right
to participate directly and indirectly in political
and public life is recognized for example in the
Universal Declaration of Human Rights (Art. 21)
(24) and the International Covenant on Civil and
Political Rights (Art. 25) (25), which has been ratied
by 173 states:
Article 25: Every citizen shall have the right
and the opportunity, without any of the
distinctions mentioned in article 2 and without
unreasonable restrictions:
(a) To take part in the conduct of public
affairs, directly or through freely chosen
representatives; ….
As the United Nations Human Rights Committee
stated, Article 25 lies at the core of democratic
government based on the consent of the people
and in conformity with the principles of the
Covenant” (General Comment No. 25, para 1). The
Committee has also made clear (para 8) (26) that
[c]itizens also take part in the conduct of
public affairs by exerting influence through
public debate and dialogue with their
representatives or through their capacity to
organize themselves. This participation is
supported by ensuring freedom of expression,
assembly and association.
In September 2016, the United Nations Human
Rights Council, concerned that many people
continued to face obstacles to the enjoyment
of their right to participate in the public aairs
of their countries, requested the Office of the
High Commissioner of Human Rights to prepare
guidelines for States on eective implementation
of Article 25 (A/HRC/RES/33/22, 6 October 2016).
The guidelines presented 2years later (A/HRC/
RES/39/11, 5 October 2018) are grounded on the
following general principle:
Participation makes decision-making
more informed and sustainable, and public
institutions more effective, accountable
and transparent. This in turn enhances the
legitimacy of States’ decisions and their
ownership by all members of society (27).
Several clarifications and recommendations of
the guidelines are directly relevant to the current
health crisis and the arguments we put forward in
this paper. The guidance emphasizes, for instance,
that Article 25 is not limited to so-called electoral
rights”, i.e. rights to participate in periodic, free,
fair elections as a voter or a candidate. It also
addresses direct and indirect participation in non-
electoral contexts, covering, broadly, all aspects
of public administration and the formulation and
implementation of policy at international, national,
regional and local levels (para 49). The instruments
for such participation include referenda, popular
assemblies, consultative bodies, public hearings, as
well as free public debate and dialogue (para 50).
Moreover, participation should be enabled at all
stages of decision-making, before, during and after
a decision is made (e.g. agenda-setting, drafting,
decision-making, implementation, monitoring and
reformulation, para 53).
The current health crisis has exposed the insucient,
fragile status of the right to participation across the
globe, including in better-established, democratic
regimes. This is a particular concern in the light of
what is at stake. As discussed above, the arsenal
of measures available to governments to respond
to pandemics includes tools that could infringe on
fundamental rights such as freedom of movement,
freedom of assembly and the right to protest, in
particular when a state of emergency is declared,
which gives the government powers that it does
not have during normal times. In this context, the
Participation as a human right
Dicult trade-os in response to COVID-19: the case for open and inclusive decision-making
6
right to participation recognized in Article 25 of
the International Covenant on Civil and Political
Rights becomes even more important, as it enables
an additional layer of popular accountability,
which can enhance the legitimacy of measures
and, by increasing acceptance of the measures,
the eectiveness of countries responses to the
health crisis.
7
Elements of open and inclusive decision-making
While acceptance of policies can improve
adherence, the complexity of the issues makes it
dicult for individuals to reach a comprehensive
conclusion about whether a policy is acceptable.
For this reason, trust in authorities – understood as
a person’s belief that another person or institution
will act consistently with their expectations of
positive behaviour” (28) – is often necessary for
acceptance. Trust in governing authorities can
result in adherence to directives in the belief
that the authorities are acting in the interests
of the people (29). Trust enables and motivates
cooperation, and thus policies are implemented
with fewer protests. In this sense, trust can forestall
the use of force to ensure compliance.
Trust is not irrational and is not automatic in new
circumstances; it must be earned (30). A major
challenge for authorities is to be and to present
themselves as trustworthy when making dicult
choices in a pandemic. To provide reasons to be
trusted, they should make themselves accountable
to the public. By describing how they manage
evidence and uncertainty and just distribution of
burdens and benets and by ensuring that policies
are decided after dialogue with the people who are
aected and are open to challenge and revision,
members of society are given opportunities to
influence and assess the authorities’ choices.
Authorities thus allow people to place justied,
and not blind, trust in their governance strategies.
The case for fair processes
In order for people to accept burdensome policies
and to adhere to them willingly, the policies must
be perceived as fair. The fairness of a decision
can be assessed substantively, in terms of its
impacts on people’s lives and freedom, and/or
procedurally, in terms of how the decision was
made (31). The assumption behind procedural
Elements of open and inclusive
decision-making
justice is that, even in the face of widespread
disagreement about the just distribution of
burdens and benefits, the affected parties can
sometimes be expected to reach agreement on
the conditions that must be in place to make
decision-making fair (32–34). Procedural fairness
allows people to consider a policy fair even though
they would have preferred another policy or are
unable to reach a conclusion on the substantive
fairness of the policy. This general framework is
broadly supported by political philosophy and
empirical research on procedural fairness (31–37)
and recognized and enforced by human rights
law (see previous section). The key arguments for
transparent, inclusive decision-making are listed
in the box.
From the perspective of political philosophy,
procedural fairness requires that decisions that
affect peoples interests are taken: (a)on the
basis of evidence; (b)with equal consideration
of everyone’s interests and of their legitimate
perspectives; (c)on the basis of reasons that people
can share, that is, recognize as relevant from their
differing views of a good life and substantive
fairness; (d)in an open, accessible manner; and (e)
through institutional means that permit challenge
and revision of decisions. Such procedures
promote inclusion, require openness and make
the decision-makers accountable, all of which
contribute to the perceived legitimacy of and trust
in the decision-makers and to adherence to the
policies (38). Evidence from empirical research on
fairness shows that peoples assessments of the
fairness of a legal decision are also inuenced by
how the decision was made (35). Fair procedures
are the aspect that determines the legitimacy of
authorities and, with that, peoples willingness to
defer to their decisions (36).
This approach might be seen as placing demanding
requirements on the capacity of the participants
Dicult trade-os in response to COVID-19: the case for open and inclusive decision-making
8
in the deliberation to reason and to propose
impartial reasons for and against policies. This
could therefore exclude the voices of those who
do not always express their concerns in such terms.
Such silencing” must be avoided to ensure that a
broad range of perspectives is heard on contested
policies, while at the same time nding ways to
lter out partial suggestions and to give equal
consideration to the expressed interests of all
(39). In particular, people who express aggressive
resistance to policies for reducing exposure to the
virus or lack of fair-mindedness in nding solutions
should be invited to contribute their perspectives
to collective deliberation (39). Their concerns
must be addressed respectfully, and, if it is found
that they cannot be accommodated, the people
involved should be given an accessible justication
of why their views cannot be determinant in the
content of the public health and social measures.
In a pandemic, the equality of concerns is crucial.
Perceived unfairness of exclusion of a persons
critical perspectives can lead to lack of adherence
and undermine the eectiveness of public health
and social measures.
Seminal socio-legal work on procedural fairness
describes the elements of decision-making and
procedural components and rules that may be
relevant for perceived fairness (40). Some of those
rules are as follows.
Consistency requires that allocative procedures
are uniform among people and over time and
that the distributions of harms and benets are
assessed according to the same standard for all.
Bias suppression requires abstinence from
exclusive promotion of self-interest and giving
up ideological preconceptions. This is important
for how broadly participants are invited and how
their views are listened to and addressed.
Accuracy demands that decisions be based
on the best available evidence and informed
opinion. Of course, robust evidence on any
harmful consequences of proposed policies
may not be available when decisions are made.
Open communication of what is not known thus
becomes essential for accurate presentation of
conclusions (41).
Correctability indicates that it must always
be possible to revise a decision in the light of
emerging reasons. This is particularly important
in an emergency or crisis, when decisions are
based on uncertain, evolving evidence. A policy
might therefore cause unforeseen harm, and new
reasons for adjusting policies might be proposed
by those aected.
Representativeness requires that the concerns,
values and perspectives of all groups in society are
presented. In a pandemic, especially when drastic
measures are necessary, it is essential to include
the voices of the people who would be adversely
aected by a potential policy. Moreover, inclusion
of representatives of subgroups by allowing them
equal opportunities to have a say on decisions
manifests actual power-sharing and democratic
inuence and thus mitigates power imbalances
(42).
We would also add that transparency and
accessibility, including for those who were
not directly involved in a decision, are crucial
for perceived fairness. These attributes broaden
the reach of the process and thus enhance the
eects of the rules on accuracy, correctability and
representativeness.
The relevance of these procedural principles
depends on the circumstances (40). For
policy-making in a pandemic, however, when
extraordinary measures are called for and the
stakes are high, these principles are important to
protect rights and ensure respect. By promoting
respect for everyones perspective, the procedures
foster and protect self-esteem and empowerment
in a crisis.
In principle, all members of the public are aected
by policies that will profoundly shape their health
and living conditions and should therefore have
the opportunity to have an input. This ideal is
realized by making all relevant information
publicly accessible for scrutiny and criticism, with
established channels for appeals.
9
Elements of open and inclusive decision-making
The role of experts
Given the importance of using evidence in fair
process, we look closely into the role of scientic
experts in deciding on public health and social
measures. The involvement of experts is core
to any fair process for public decision-making,
because the public has the right to decisions
that are as well-informed as possible. Ideally,
research facilitates policy-making by providing
well-confirmed models or generalizations that
indicate the possible consequences of dierent
scenarios that are relevant to local decision-
makers(43,44). Trustworthy decision-making thus
involves experts and builds on the evidence they
provide as far as possible. It is, however, dicult to
ensure that the manner in which experts interact
with the public is consistent with the democratic
and participatory principles that this report seeks
to advance (45), and the principles that should
guide such interactions should be formulated.
Generally, we agree with and generalize the claim
by Gurdasani et al. (46) that
governments […] ought to conduct regular
briefing and be open, honest, and transparent
about where we are. [They] must admit to
and learn from mistakes, not overstate [their]
capabilities and achievements, and must
treat the public as equal partners, working
with communities to develop effective health
promotion strategies.
For achievement of this ideal, we highlight three
high-level principles to guide governments and
expert bodies. Experts should communicate in a
way that is (i) transparent with regard to empirical
uncertainties, (ii) transparent with regard to values
and (iii) receptive to public feedback.
It is inevitable that action must sometimes be
taken before scientic enquiry allows anything
like certainty (47). This is true especially in this
pandemic, with uncertainty about the values
of key parameters, about relevant causal
mechanisms and about how people will respond
to novel events. In order to reason about these
uncertainties sensibly, the public should be made
aware of where the uncertainties arise and how
they may be dealt with (48). The way in which
uncertainties are represented can make a huge
difference to what kinds of decisions can be
supported rationally (49–51). Further, the public is
highly sensitive to expressions of disagreement or
uncertainty by scientists (52,53). If people are not
appropriately informed about what uncertainties
mean, they will be open to manipulation by well-
resourced groups acting in bad faith (52,53). More
generally, in order to combat the “infodemic” of
misinformation spreading on social media, which
is interfering with rational attempts to address
COVID-19, transparent, frank dialogue should be
maintained among scientists, policy-makers and
the broader public (54).
In order to justify a particular approach to addressing
uncertainties, scientists must often appeal to ethical
or political values in deciding which risks are worth
taking more seriously than others (55). Such value-
laden decisions affect not only what scientists
consider to be true but how they communicate
their uncertainties and the measures they used
to weigh and assess the outcomes of interest.
Science communication should hence prioritize
communication of the nature of the value-laden
decisions that scientists must make, including what
the stakes are and how the legitimate interests of
dierent parties are assessed and weighed.
People who communicate science should ensure
that scientists are appropriately receptive to public
feedback, including challenges to their knowledge.
They should therefore themselves understand
that public input into research can be legitimate
and important, and they should be receptive to
bidirectional communication between the public
and scientic experts.
In considering how these principles for science
communication can be put into practice, policy-
makers can draw on a wealth of examples. For
instance, “mini” public exercises have been
conducted in which experts are called as “witnesses”
by deliberative panels of citizens and asked to
explain points such as What we are uncertain about
and why”, “Whose interests are at stake, followed
by questioning and scrutiny by representatives of
the public (56). Work is under way to update these
models with respect to COVID-19 (57).
Dicult trade-os in response to COVID-19: the case for open and inclusive decision-making
10
Difficulty in meeting the conditions for fair
processes discussed above differs by country.
Some experiences have been positive. Countries
that have managed to mitigate the socioeconomic
impacts of the pandemic include both those with
authoritarian regimes and democracies and both
low- and high-income countries. Many countries
with weak, untrustworthy institutions, scarce
health care resources and budgets, and limited
scal space will be unable or unwilling to meet
all the requirements of fair processes and fair
conditions, some because of structural constraints
(e.g. weak institutions or limited scal capacity)
and others because they are unwilling to engage
with all the parties aected.
A particular set of challenges stems from
inequality. There is preliminary evidence that
countries with greater income inequality tend to
have higher numbers of deaths from COVID-19,
partly because the poorest have high risks of
infection and limited access to treatment and
partly because high inequality reduces trust in
government institutions (14). South Africa, which
is the country with the most inequality in the
world, has the highest mortality rate on the African
continent and twice the world average number of
deaths per million. Brazil, the Russian Federation
and the USA, where there are wide gaps between
the rich and the poor, have also experienced high
number of deaths from the virus. A deadly surge
of cases is being experienced in Lebanon (21,58),
the most unequal country in the Arab world
(Gini index 50.7), and its population is facing a
concatenation of crises – socioeconomic, banking,
nancial, political, humanitarian, environmental
and sanitary – with more than half of its population
now poor. Other challenges face Latin America,
which has some of the highest rates of mortality
due to COVID-19. Peru is among the hardest hit
countries (59). While the Peruvian Government’s
initial response appeared to be exemplary (a
Challenges for vulnerable
countries
swift, strict lockdown and a generous economic
package), the pandemic exposed the fragility of
an emerging state with weak and untrustworthy
institutions, a weak, deeply unequal health care
system, a high level of corruption and a large
informal sector. Hence, generally, the more equal
(albeit poor) a society is, the more likely are fair
processes; conversely, the more unequal a society
is, the more challenging it will be to meet the
conditions of fair process.
Lack of trust in governments and institutions in
these contexts is a major obstacle to compliance
with public health and social measures (28) and
also to nding common ground among all aected
parties. Nonetheless, these countries could improve
decision-making processes under COVID-19. At
a minimum, civil society and nongovernmental
organizations could mobilize and join eorts to
make sure that their governments:
intervene early in a cooperative, transparent
manner that includes all private and
public stakeholders and especially local
communities;
communicate clearly, frequently and
consistently with the public both online
and through traditional channels of
communication. Because of widespread
mistrust in ocial sources, authorities could
enlist the help of civil society organizations,
village councils and religious and traditional
leaders to disseminate information and
engage with communities in finding
workable strategies (18);
make health-related data openly available,
and consult experts as widely as possible in
an open, transparent way, both for countering
disinformation and to help all aected parties
in making evidence-based decisions;
11
Challenges for vulnerable countries
ensure that grants and funds received from
international organizations are well spent
and allocated to social and health sectors. The
International Monetary Fund has approved
debt service relief via grants to the 29 poorest
countries and has provided lines of credit
(US$ 100 billion) to 81 countries (60–62).
While this support is vital, the decisions
were taken in an unprecedented expeditious
manner, with few checks and balances to
ensure compliance with the terms of the
loans and the commitments of countries to
reallocate the funds appropriately to crisis
mitigation. The Fund has stated its intent to
monitor emergency lending, but it has yet
to publish or share the detailed mechanism
for each country that has voiced its “intent”
to reallocate funds to COVID-19 (63). Given
the signicant increase in lending to poor
countries, the organizations involved do
not have the capacity to monitor the
conditions of their loans as carefully as in
the past. Moreover, as called for in the Paris
Declaration on Aid Eectiveness (2005) and
the Accra Declaration for Action (2008), the
participation of local nongovernmental
and civil society organizations is essential
in pressuring governments to spend the
funds appropriately, hence enhancing their
eectiveness (64); and
try to regain public trust and condence by
ensuring open, inclusive, and transparent
decision-making. While it is true that in
Kerala, a poor but equal Indian state, trust
in local authorities was a prerequisite for
the implementation of pro-active public
health and social measures, the transparent,
comprehensive strategy that was successfully
implemented also helped reinforce that pre-
existing public trust to the extent that state
actions were complemented by voluntary
actions by the people: wealthy families
donated their homes for quarantine and
isolation, village councils monitored cases
locally, and students volunteered to set up
COVID-test kiosks in their neighbourhoods (65).
Dicult trade-os in response to COVID-19: the case for open and inclusive decision-making
12
After decades of lobbying by patient groups and
civil society organizations, a growing number of
countries have institutionalized systems for more
open, inclusive decision-making, including for
health. In many countries, this has been developed
within the Open Government Partnership (66). With
few exceptions, however, these systems have been
side-lined during the COVID-19 pandemic, leading
to poorer decisions and preventable deaths (67,68).
Notable exceptions are the Republic of Korea
and Taiwan (China), where inclusive decision-
making has been seen as central to their successful
responses to the pandemic.
Several countries with a history of inclusive
health governance and systems appear to have
benetted from those systems to some extent in
the early stages of the pandemic, although they
were not used to their full capacity. Successful
COVID-19 responses have been ascribed partly
to a reservoir of trust in the public health system
and in authorities and to eective communication
strategies and social support mechanisms that
ensured compliance. These have been linked to
previous practices of stakeholder participation and
health democracy and to unied, robust public
health systems. As the strains of the pandemic
increase, trust is wearing thin in most countries,
and decision-making systems must urgently be
revitalized and made inclusive.
Experimentation with inclusive, deliberative
decision-making provides useful guidance on
making the process more inclusive, transparent
and accountable in the context of the COVID-19
pandemic (68,70). Many participatory mechanisms
have been introduced throughout the world in
recent years to improve the quality and legitimacy
of public decision-making, including in health. A
catalogue, including initiatives taken in relation
to COVID-19, can be found at https://participedia.
Experiences of participatory
processes in the context of
COVID-19
net/. Studies have shown that when such initiatives
were carefully set up and implemented, they were
useful and robust, indicating that they could be
promising for the type of decision-making required
in response to COVID-19, involving value-based
questions and complex trade-os (71).
As discussed above, four groups of actors must
be included in decisions: scientists and experts
in relevant elds; stakeholders who can express
the concerns of aected groups (such as patient
associations, trade unions, cooperatives and
student organizations); members of the public
more broadly and especially members of groups
that are likely to be missed by stakeholder
associations; and the politicians responsible for
making the decisions.
Some deliberative processes, such as certain large
assemblies of citizens, can and have included all
four types of actor; however, most participatory
mechanisms centre on one or two groups. For
complex decisions that must be taken quickly and
revised regularly, complementary processes and
mechanisms may have to be coordinated. From
a pragmatic point of view, it is thus important to
identify the existing participatory mechanisms
that contribute to COVID-19-related decision-
making and to consider how they can best be
integrated, not least in ensuring that public and
stakeholder deliberations are informed by and
inform scientic expertise. The elements that can
and increasingly do form part of such systems
include the following.
(i) Inclusive deliberative bodies set up to include
relevant voices and provide well-considered
advice, “mini-publics, may consist only of
randomly selected members of the public or also
include experts, stakeholders and/or politicians.
Even when they are not members, experts and
13
Experiences of participatory processes in the context of COVID-19
organized stakeholders are usually brought
in to provide evidence and answer questions.
Some of these deliberative forums are large,
ad-hoc citizens assemblies, while others are
permanent public panels set up to address new
issues as they arise, and others are advisory
councils with expertise in a particular area.
Such bodies, when properly constituted, can
be particularly useful for reaching trustworthy,
legitimate decisions on dicult ethical questions
and complex trade-os.A great advantage of
these bodies, besides the deliberative process,
which allows views to be shaped and reshaped
in the light of evidence and arguments, is that
they are often broadly representative of the
population and ensure inclusion of particularly
affected groups. Deliberative forums have
always been held face-to-face, over several days,
but are increasingly conducted online, often at
shorter intervals. While certain groups may face
practical challenges of technical access, online
communication is relatively easy to facilitate for
limited, selected bodies. Examples of deliberative
bodies that have been set up and used in the
context of the pandemic include: the COVID-19
Culturally and Linguistically Diverse Community
Forums (72) and a Deliberative Consultation on
Trade-os Related to Using COVIDSafe” Contact
Tracing Technology (73) in Australia, the Oregon
Citizens Assembly on COVID-19 recovery in
the USA (74) and planning recovery in the West
Midlands by a citizens’ panel in England (75).
The last is a good example of coordination
among different mechanisms. It was formed
to represent a cross-section of the public by
the West Midlands Recovery Co-ordination
Group (which itself is a collaboration among
local authorities, emergency services and local
enterprise partnerships) to complement the
Economic Impact Group, which consists of
business leaders, central Government, banks,
trade unions and local authorities.
(ii) Hearings are institutionalized in many countries
to gain insights from experts and stakeholders
on draft legislation and policy. Their advantages,
particularly when they are mandated in laws
and regulations, are that they are closely linked
to formal decision-making and can inform and
spur public debate and confer legitimacy on
decisions for interested stakeholders. Most
importantly, they can increase the knowledge
base and enhance the quality of deliberations by
governments and legislatures by broadening the
points of view and interests considered. Hearings
do not, however, have an inclusive, deliberated
output, as the participants in hearings do not
jointly deliberate difficult ethical issues or
trade-os. As submissions are usually public,
participants often engage with the considered
views of adversaries. Most institutionalized
hearings are not open to the general public.
Mandated consultations with indigenous
peoples, set up to protect their autonomy
and rights, could be extended to COVID-19-
related decisions, as indigenous groups are
particularly vulnerable (76–78). Hearings related
to the pandemic have been conducted in
Norway on the “Corona-law and changes in
the regulation; however, although mandated in
law, it was enacted only after lobbying by civil
society groups, academics and the National
Human Rights Institution (79). In the USA, where
hearings are optional, the National Academies
of Sciences Engineering and Medicine provided
opportunities for public comment on a draft of a
Preliminary Framework for Equitable Allocation
of COVID-19 Vaccine (80).
Most of the public participation and inclusive
decision-making initiatives that have emerged in
the pandemic, belong, however to the third type
of element.
(iii) Open, self-selective public participation
mechanisms. Such mechanisms are set up by
national or subnational governments or by civil
society to ensure that, in principle, everyone
can make their voice heard. They take a variety
of forms, including deliberative “town halls”
and village or municipal meetings, which may
be face-to-face or, increasingly, online in the
form of “virtual democracy platforms”, radio and
television call-in shows, calls for petitions and
crowd-sourcing of legal provisions, guidelines
and policies through Wikipedia-style” drafting
and editing. Mechanisms are often set up to
collect the participatory input and make it
available to decision-makers, and eorts are
made to determine how the input is taken
Dicult trade-os in response to COVID-19: the case for open and inclusive decision-making
14
into account in decision-making. A common
criticism of these mechanisms is that they are
used de facto more often by those with the
most resources and do not usually ensure that
the views of the most vulnerable are enabled
or represented (69,81). Online platforms are
crucial in facilitating such mechanisms, not least
during the pandemic, but, unlike organized
mini-publics”, for which variable access to the
Internet and technology can be compensated,
access is a greater barrier to open participation.
Mechanisms for public engagement related to
COVID are many and diverse (for more examples,
see https://participedia.net/collection/6501).
In Scotland, a national crowd-sourcing exercise
was undertaken to create a framework for
decision-making in the context of COVID-19, in
which the Government “sought public input on
the on approaches and principles that would
guide decision making related to transitioning
out of the coronavirus (COVID-19) lockdown
arrangements” (82). In Brazil, the federal health
system has set up an extensive mechanism
for transparency and public engagement in
COVID-19 (83); Senegal has established several
citizen initiatives (84,85); and civil society
in Lebanon has set up the Independent
Committee for the Elimination of COVID-19 (86).
In the United Kingdom, the Government expert
body, SAGE (87), has a civil society counterpart
in Independent SAGE (88). In the USA,
deliberative town halls on COVID-19 are set up
by Connecting to Congress (89), and academics
oer an ambitious transnational resource for
public engagement, Endcoronavirus.org (90).
A participatory system of government for
answering complex questions will usually consist
of a combination of mechanisms to involve
different groups for different purposes. To
serve their purpose and build public trust, they
should be institutionalized rather than ad hoc,
thus making inclusive, transparent, accountable
decision-making a routine feature of governance,
beyond the pandemic, as part of eorts to build
back better.
15
Concluding remarks
Deliberative decision-making that is inclusive,
transparent and accountable gives everyone a
say in decisions that may profoundly aect them.
It respects people’s ability to offer, assess and
act on reasons and is required by the principles
of human rights and the rule of law. Crucially,
evidence even before COVID-19 showed that
this kind of decision-making can contribute to
more trustworthy, more legitimate decisions on
Concluding remarks
dicult ethical questions and challenging trade-
os. Institutionalising and broadening deliberative
processes should therefore be a priority in the
pandemic response. In the short term, it can build
legitimacy and support for the dicult decisions
that must be made in response to the pandemic
and prevent further erosion of trust. In the long
term, it can contribute to virtuous cycles of trust-
building and more eective policies.
Dicult trade-os in response to COVID-19: the case for open and inclusive decision-making
16
Box. Open, inclusive decision-making under COVID-19
A. SUPPORTING REASONS
Political equality and human rights
Inclusive decision-making ensures that governments act according to the rights of political participation enshrined in national
and international law, in particular human rights law and the principles of accountable government.
Broad-based, transparent decision-making fulls the ideal of procedural fairness, which requires that decisions that aect
peoples’ interests be taken: on the basis of evidence; with equal consideration of everyone’s interests and perspectives; on the
basis of reasons that people can share; in an open, accessible manner; and through institutional means that permit challenge
and revision of decisions.
Inclusive decision-making rests on the democratic ideal that all people should have a fair opportunity to participate in decisions
that aect them.
Inclusion of all those aected promotes self-esteem and mutual respect.
Transparency allows the public to form informed opinions.
When decisions are based on reasons that can be appreciated by all, such as the importance of protecting health and limiting
economic impact, all participants are considered capable of understanding and acting on those common reasons.
Procedurally fair decision-making processes contribute to trust in decision-makers and to the legitimacy of the decisions.
Inclusive decision-making may lessen social disagreement, because, even in the face of polarized opinions about what to do, it
may nonetheless be possible to achieve agreement on fair procedures for arriving at policy decisions. Policies resulting from fair
procedures may then be accepted even by those who disagree with them on substantive grounds.
Restrictions on freedom are more readily accepted if they are the outcome of a fair process. Acceptance reduces the burden of
restrictions and renders them more consistent with autonomy.
Eective communication
Policy decisions are better targeted and more eective if they are informed by accurate descriptions of the circumstances and
evidence of what works.
Critical scrutiny of evidence and uncertainty can improve decisions.
Communication of clear rationales and uncertainty engenders trust.
Transparent, publicly accessible evidence prevents disinformation and builds trust.
Trust and adherence
Open, inclusive decision-making builds trust. This improves adherence to policies, making them more eective. Greater
eectiveness, in turn, engenders more trust in policy-makers. Open decision-making can therefore contribute to a virtuous
cycle of increasing trust, adherence and policy eectiveness.
17
Concluding remarks
Box. Open, inclusive decision-making under COVID-19 (continued)
B. KEY ELEMENTS
Political leaders
Decision-making is built on evidence.
The ethical, legal, scientic, economic, social and political reasons for a decision are transparent.
In order to facilitate consensus, as far as possible, the reasons can be shared by people with dissimilar moral and political
outlooks.
Decisions and their rationale are communicated in a manner that everyone can understand.
Experts
Experts are drawn from a variety of elds, including the humanities and medical and social sciences.
Experts communicate transparently about what works and for whom and about uncertainty and values.
Experts publish their ndings and recommendations for critical scrutiny.
Epidemiological, statistical and other relevant national data are open to access.
Experts participate in forums that leave them open to critical feedback and adjust those elements of their practice that are
legitimately challenged by members of the public.
The public
All aected parties are included, listened to and have a say.
Special attention is given to vulnerable and marginalized groups and to the perceived harm and benets to people who cannot
easily raise their voices.
Accountability
All aected individuals and groups can challenge decisions.
Mechanisms are in place for feedback and revision when new challenges or evidence emerge.
The input of aected parties is documented.
Mechanisms are in place for budgetary transparency and ensuring that loans and grants are allocated appropriately.
Dicult trade-os in response to COVID-19: the case for open and inclusive decision-making
18
Box. Open, inclusive decision-making under COVID-19 (continued)
C. PRACTICAL EXAMPLES
Countries with established systems of participatory health governance, even when they are not used, benet from a base of public
trust, which, with eective communication strategies and unied public health systems are central to a successful COVID-19
response. Examples include: Mongolia (91,92), New Zealand (93,94) and Rwanda (95).
Elements of systems for open and inclusive decision-making include:
Inclusive deliberative bodies: ad-hoc citizens’ assemblies, permanent citizens’ panels, advisory councils
Australia: COVID-19 Culturally and Linguistically Diverse Community Forums: South Australia (72)
England: Citizens Panel Planning the West Midlands Recovery (75)
USA: Oregon Citizens’ Assembly on COVID-19 Recovery (74)
Hearings: mandated in law or optional
France: Commission d’enquête pour l’évaluation des politiques publiques face aux grandes pandémies à la lumière de la crise
sanitaire de la COVID-19 et de sa gestion (96)
Norway: Corona-law and regulation changes (79)
USA: National Academies of Sciences Engineering and Medicine. Public Comment Opportunities: Discussion Draft of the
Preliminary Framework for Equitable Allocation of COVID-19 Vaccine (80)
Open, self-selective public participation mechanisms: town halls, village meetings (face-to-face or online), radio and
television call-in programmes, petitions and crowd–sourcing, initiated by either government or civil society
Brazil: mechanism for transparency and public engagement on COVID-19 in the federal health system (83)
France: Citizens’ committee in Grenoble (97)
Lebanon: Independent Committee for the Elimination of COVID-19 (86)
Scotland: Coronavirus (COVID-19): framework for decision-making, national crowd-sourcing exercise (82)
Senegal: several citizens’ initiatives (84,85)
United Kingdom: Independent SAGE (88)
USA: Connecting to Congress, deliberative town halls on COVID-19 (89) and Endcoronavirus.org (90)
19
References
References
1. Alwan NA, Burgess RA, Ashworth S, Beale R, Bhadelia N, Bogaert D, et al. Scientic consensus on the COVID-19 pandemic:
we need to act now. Lancet. 2020;396(10260):e71–2.
2. Fontanet A, Cauchemez S. COVID-19 herd immunity: where are we? Nat Rev Immunol. 2020;20(10):583–4.
3. Brazeau N, Verity R, Jenks S, Fu H, Whittaker C, Winskill P, et al. Supplementary data – report 34: COVID-19 infection fatality
ratio: estimates from seroprevalence. London: Imperial College; 2020 (https://www.imperial.ac.uk/media/imperial-
college/medicine/mrc-gida/2020-10-29-COVID19-Report-34-supplement.pdf, accessed 22 November 2020).
4. Finch WH, Hernandez Finch M. Poverty and Covid-19: Rates of incidence and deaths in the United States during the rst
10 weeks of the pandemic. Front Sociol. 2020:doi.org/10.3389/fsoc.2020.00047.
5. Koh D. Migrant workers and COVID-19. Occup Environ Med. 2020;77(9):634–6.
6. Deaths involving COVID-19 by local area and socioeconomic deprivation: deaths occurring between 1 March and 31
July 2020. London: Oce for National Statistics; 2020 (https://www.ons.gov.uk/peoplepopulationandcommunity/
birthsdeathsandmarriages/deaths/bulletins/deathsinvolvingcovid19bylocalareasanddeprivation/
deathsoccurringbetween1marchand31july2020, accessed 3 November 2020).
7. Flaxman S, Mishra S, Gandy A, Unwin HJT, Coupland H, Mellan TA, et al. Report 13 – Estimating the number of infections
and the impact of non-pharmaceutical interventions on COVID-19 in 11 European countries. London: Imperial College;
2020 (https://www.imperial.ac.uk/mrc-global-infectious-disease-analysis/covid-19/report-13-europe-npi-impact,
accessed 22 November 2020).
8. Fleurbaey MF. COVID policy simulator. Paris: Ecole d’Economie de Paris; 2020 (https://sites.google.com/site/
marceurbaey/Home/covid?authuser=0, accessed 22 November 2020).
9. Miles D, Stedman M, Heald A. Living with COVID-19: Balancing costs against benets in the face of the virus. Natl Inst Econ
Rev. 2020;253:R60–76.
10. Chu DK, Akl EA, Duda S, Solo K, Yaacoub S, Schünemann HJ, et al. Physical distancing, face masks, and eye protection to
prevent person-to-person transmission of SARS-CoV-2 and COVID-19: a systematic review and meta-analysis. Lancet.
2020;395(10242):1973–87.
11. Lazar S, Sheel M. Contact tracing apps are vital tools in the ght against coronavirus. But who decides how theywork?
The Conversation, 12 May 2020 (https://theconversation.com/contact-tracing-apps-are-vital-tools-in-the-ght-against-
coronavirus-but-who-decides-how-they-work-138206, accessed 22 November 2020).
12. World economic outlook, October 2020. Washington DC: International Monetary Fund; 2020 (https://www.imf.org/en/
Publications/WEO/Issues/2020/09/30/world-economic-outlook-october-2020 (accessed 30 October 2020).
13. Layard R, Clark A, De Neve JE, Krekel C, Fancourt D, Hey N, et al. When to release the lockdown: A wellbeing framework for
analysing costs and benets (Occasional Paper 49). London: Centre for Economic Performance; 2020 (http://cep.lse.ac.uk/
pubs/download/occasional/op049.pdf, accessed 22 November 2020).
14. Elgar FJ, Stefaniak A, Wohl MJA. The trouble with trust: Time-series analysis of social capital, income inequality, and
COVID-19 deaths in 84 countries. Soc Sci Med. 2020;263:113365.
15. COVID-19 and indigenous peoples. New York City (NY): United Nations; 2020 (https://www.un.org/development/desa/
indigenouspeoples/covid-19.html, accessed 10 November 2020).
16. Quayyum SN, Kangni Kpodar RK. Supporting migrants and remittances as COVID-19 rages on. IMF Blog, 11 September
2020. Washington DC: International Monetary Fund; 2020 (https://blogs.imf.org/2020/09/11/supporting-migrants-and-
remittances-as-covid-19-rages-on, accessed 10 November 2020).
17. Ray D, Subramanian S. An interim report on India’s lockdown (Working paper 27282). Cambridge (MA): National Bureau of
Economic Research; 2020.
18. Diwan I, Abi-Rached JM. Killer lockdowns. Economic Research Forum Policy Portal, 21 April 2020. Giza: Economic Research
Forum; 2020 (https://theforum.erf.org.eg/2020/04/18/killer-lockdowns, accessed 10 November 2020).
19. Closing schools for covid-19 does lifelong harm and widens inequality. The Economist, 30 April 2020(https://www.
economist.com/international/2020/04/30/closing-schools-for-covid-19-does-lifelong-harm-and-widens-inequality,
accessed 12 November 2020).
Dicult trade-os in response to COVID-19: the case for open and inclusive decision-making
20
20. Global economic prospects, June 2020. Washngton DC: The World Bank; 2020 (https://openknowledge.worldbank.org/
handle/10986/33748, accessed 10 November 2020).
21. Abi-Rached JM, Ishac Diwan I. The socioeconomic impact of COVID-19 on Lebanon: A crisis within crises. Barcelona:
European Institute of the Mediterranean; 2020 (https://www.euromesco.net/publication/the-socioeconomic-impact-of-
covid-19-on-lebanon-a-crisis-within-crises/, accessed 14 November 2020).
22. Adler M, Bradley R, Ferranna M, Fleurbaey M, Voorhoeve A. How to assess the wellbeing impacts of the COVID-19
pandemic and three policy types: suppression, control, and uncontrolled spread (CEPS Policy Brief). London: Centre
for Economic Performance; 2020 (https://www.uib.no/sites/w3.uib.no/les/attachments/t20_working_paper_alex_
voorhoeve_et_al_assessing_wellbeing_impacts_of_covid-19_july_17_2020.pdf, accessed 13 November 2020).
23. Mill JS. On liberty. Kitchener: Batoche Books; 1859 [2001] (https://socialsciences.mcmaster.ca/econ/ugcm/3ll3/mill/liberty.
pdf, accessed 12 November 2020).
24. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights. General Assembly resolution 217 A. New York City (NY): United Nations.
25. International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights. Adopted and opened for signature, ratication and accession by
General Assembly resolution 2200A (XXI) of 16 December 1966, entry into force 23 March 1976, in accordance with Article
49. New York City (NY): United Nations Oce of the High Commissioner for Human Rights; 1966.
26. Equal participation in political and public aairs. Resolution adopted by the Human Rights Council on 30 September
2016. United Nations A/HRC/RES/33/22. Geneva: The Human Rights Council; 2016.
27. Guidelines for States on the eective implementation of the right to participate in public aairs. Geneva: United Nations
Oce of the High Commissioner for Human Rights; 2018.
28. OECD guidelines on measuring trust. Paris: Organization for Economic Co-operation and Development; 2017.
29. Warren ME. Democratic theory and trust. In: Hardin R, Oe C, editors. Democracy and trust. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press; 1999:310.
30. Baier A. Trust and antitrust. Ethics. 1986;96(2):231–60.
31. Daniels N, Sabin JE. Setting limits fairly: Learning to share resources for health. 2nd edition. Oxford: Oxford University
Press; 2008.
32. Rawls J. Political liberalism. New York City (NY): Columbia University Press; 1993.
33. Gutmann A, Thompson DF. Why deliberative democracy? Princeton (NJ): Princeton University Press; 2004.
34. Gutmann A, Thompson D. Democracy and disagreement. Cambridge (MA): Belknap Press of Harvard University Press;
1996.
35. Miller DT. Disrespect and the experience of injustice. Annu Rev Psychol. 2001;52(1):527–53.
36. Tyler TR. Psychological perspectives on legitimacy and legitimation. Annu Rev Psychol.2006;57:375–400.
37. Dryzek JS, Bächtiger A, Chambers S, Cohen J, Druckman JN, Felicetti A, et al. The crisis of democracy and the science of
deliberation. Science. 2019;363(6432):1144–6.
38. Jansen MPM, Baltussen R, Bærøe K. Stakeholder participation for legitimate priority setting: A checklist. Int J Health Policy
Manag. 2018;7(11):973–6.
39. Bærøe K, Baltussen R. Legitimate healthcare limit setting in a real-world setting: Integrating accountability for
reasonableness and multi-criteria decision analysis. Public Health Ethics. 2014;7(2):98–111.
40. Leventhal GS. What should be done with equity theory? In: Gergen KJ, Greenberg MS, Willis RS, editors. Social exchange.
Boston (MA): Springer; 1980:27–55.
41. Davey Smith G, Blastland M, Munafò M. Covid-19’s known unknowns. BMJ. 2020;371:m3979.
42. Baltussen R, Jansen M, Bijlmakers L. Stakeholder participation on the path to universal health coverage: the use of
evidence-informed deliberative processes. Trop Med Int Health. 2018;23(10):1071–4.
43. Cartwright N. Presidential address: Will this policy work for you? Predicting eectiveness better: How philosophy helps.
Philos Sci. 2012;79(5):973–89.
44. Parker W. Conrmation and adequacy-for-purpose in climate modelling. Proc Aristotelian Soc. 2009;83:233–49.
45. Holst C, Molander A. Public deliberation and the fact of expertise: making experts accountable. Soc Epistemol.
2017;31(3):235–50.
21
References
46. Gurdasani D, Bear L, Bogaert D, Burgess RA, Busse R, Cacciola R, et al. The UK needs a sustainable strategy for COVID-19.
Lancet. 2020; doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(20)32350-3.
47. Heesen R. How much evidence should one collect? Philos Stud. 2015;172(9):2299–313.
48. MacKenzie MK, O’Doherty K. Deliberating future issues: Minipublics and salmon genomics. J Public Deliberation.
2011;7(1):5.
49. Bradley R, Helgeson C, Hill B. Climate change assessments: condence, probability, and decision. Philos Sci.
2017;84(3):500–22.
50. Bradley R, Steele K. Making climate decisions. Philos Compass. 2015;10(11):799–810.
51. Helgeson C. Structuring decisions under deep uncertainty. Topoi. 2020;39(2):257–69.
52. Oreskes N, Conway EM. Merchants of doubt: How a handful of scientists obscured the truth on issues from tobacco smoke
to global warming. New York City (NY): Bloomsbury Publishing; 2011.
53. Weatherall JO, O’Connor C, Bruner JP. How to beat science and inuence people: Policymakers and propaganda in
epistemic networks. Br J Philos Sci. 2019;1–30.
54. Lewandowsky S, Smillie L, Garcia D, Hertwig R, Weatherall J, Egidy S, et al. Technology and democracy: Understanding
the inuence of online technologies on political behaviour and decision-making. Luxembourg: Publications Oce of the
European Union; 2020.
55. Ward ZB. On value-laden science. Stud History Philos Sci A.2020.
56. Roberts JJ, Lightbody R, Low R, Elstub S. Experts and evidence in deliberation: scrutinising the role of witnesses and
evidence in mini-publics, a case study.Policy Sci. 2020;53:3–32.
57. What role should the public play in the COVID-19 recovery? A democratic response to COVID-19. London: Involve;
2020(https://www.involve.org.uk/our-work/our-projects/guidance/what-role-should-public-play-covid-19-recovery,
accessed 10 November 2020).
58. Diwan I, Abi-Rached JM. Lebanon: Managing Covid-19 in the time of revolution. Paris: Arab Reform Initiative; 2020
(https://www.arab-reform.net/publication/managing-covid-19-in-the-time-of-revolution/, accessed 14 November 2020).
59. Peru is heading towards a dangerous new populism. The Economist, 23 July 2020 https://www.economist.com/the-
americas/2020/07/23/peru-is-heading-towards-a-dangerous-new-populism, accessed 14 November 2020).
60. COVID-19 nancial assistance and debt service relief. Washington DC: International Monetary Fund; 2020 (https://www.
imf.org/en/Topics/imf-and-covid19/COVID-Lending-Tracker, accessed 14 November 2020).
61. The IMF’s response to COVID-19. Washington DC: International Monetary Fund; 2020 (https://www.imf.org/en/About/
FAQ/imf-response-to-covid-19#q1.2, accessed 14 November 2020).
62. IMF policy paper: Catastrophe containment and relief trust: Approval of grant assistance for debt service relief.
Washington DC: International Monetary Fund; 2020 (https://www.imf.org/en/Publications/Policy-Papers/
Issues/2020/04/16/Catastrophe-Containment-And-Relief-Trust-Approval-Of-Grant-Assistance-For-Debt-Service-
Relief-49330, accessed 14 November 2020).
63. Questions and answers. How can we be sure the IMF’s emergency money doesn’t get wasted?Washington DC:
International Monetary Fund; 2020 (https://www.imf.org/en/About/FAQ/imf-response-to-covid-19#Q9, accessed 14
November 2020).
64. The Paris Declaration on Aid Eectiveness and the Accra Agenda for Action. Paris: Organization for Economic Co-
operation and Development; 2005/2008 (https://www.oecd.org/dac/eectiveness/34428351.pdf, accessed 14 November
2020).
65. Jalan J, Arijit Sen A. Containing a pandemic with public actions and public trust: The Kerala story. Indian Econ Rev.
2020;1–20.
66. Public services health. Open Government Partnershipglobal report: Democracy beyond the ballot box. Washington
DC: Open Government Partnership; 2019 (https://www.opengovpartnership.org/wp-content/uploads/2019/08/Global-
Report_Health.pdf, accessed 5 November 2020).
67. Casassus B. Covid-19: French sidelining of patient associations is a global trend. BMJ. 2020;371:m4082.
68. Richards T, Scowcroft H, BMJ’s international patient and public advisory panel. Patient and public involvement in covid-19
policy making. BMJ. 2020;370:m2575.
69. Smith G. Democratic innovations: Designing institutions for citizen participation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press;
2009.
Dicult trade-os in response to COVID-19: the case for open and inclusive decision-making
22
70. Dean R, Boswell J, Smith G. Designing democratic innovations as deliberative systems: The ambitious case of NHS citizen.
Polit Stud. 2020;68(3):689–709.
71. Innovative citizen participation and new democratic institutions: Catching the deliberative wave. Paris: Organization for
Economic Co-operation and Development Publishing, 2020 (https://doi.org/10.1787/339306da-en, accessed 1 November
2020).
72. COVID-19. Culturally & linguistically diverse community forums: South Australia. Vancouver: Participedia; 2020(https://
participedia.net/case/7086, accessed 4 November 2020).
73. Deliberative consultation on trade-os related to using “COVIDSafe contact tracing technology. Vancouver: Participedia;
2020(https://participedia.net/case/6573, accessed 14 November 2020).
74. Oregon Citizens’ Assembly on COVID-19 recovery. Vancouver: Participedia; 2020(https://participedia.net/case/7114,
accessed 4 November 2020).
75. Citizens’ panel – Planning the West Midlands’ recovery. Vancouver: Participedia; 2020 https://participedia.net/case/7085,
accessed 4 November 2020).
76. Charlier P, Varison L. Is COVID-19 being used as a weapon against indigenous peoples in Brazil? Lancet.
2020;396(10257):1069–70.
77. Urteaga-Crovetto P. Implementation of the right to prior consultation in the Andean countries. A comparative
perspective. J Legal Pluralism Unocial Law. 2018;50(1):7–30.
78. Indigenous peoples and the COVID-19 pandemic. Paris: United Nations Educational, Scientic and Cultural Organization;
2020 (https://en.unesco.org/news/indigenous-peoples-and-covid-19-pandemic, accessed 5 November 2020).
79. Koronaloven og høringer [Corona law and hearings]. Oslo: Government of Norway; 2020(https://www.regjeringen.no/
no/tema/Koronasituasjonen/forskrifter-med-hjemmel-i-koronaloven/koronaloven-og-forskriftsendringer/id2695161/,
accessed 3 November 2020).
80. Public comment opportunities: Discussion draft of the preliminary framework for equitable allocation of COVID-19
vaccine. Washington DC: National Academies of Sciences Engineering and Medicine; 2020(https://www.
nationalacademies.org/our-work/a-framework-for-equitable-allocation-of-vaccine-for-the-novel-coronavirus/
announcement/public-comment-opportunities, accessed 1 September 2020).
81. Spada P, Ryan M. The failure to examine failures in democratic innovations. Political Sci Politics. 2017;50(3):772–8.
82. Coronavirus (COVID-19): framework for decision making – national crowdsourcing exercise. Vancouver: Participedia; 2020
(https://participedia.net/case/6667, accessed 4 November 2020).
83. Recomendações 2020 [Recommendations 2020]. Brasilia: Conselho National de Saúde; 2020 (http://conselho.saude.gov.
br/recomendacoes-cns, accessed 5 November 2020).
84. COVID-19 et technologie civique au Sénégal [COVID-19 and civic technology in Senegal]. Dakar: Heinrich-Böll-Stiftung;
2020 (https://sn.boell.org/fr/2020/07/21/covid-19-et-technologie-civique-au-senegal, accessed 5 November 2020).
85. Lucienne M, Odiaua I, Yamouri N. World Bank blog: Senegal’s youth oers inspiring creativity to ght COVID-19.
Washington DC: The World Bank; 2020 (https://blogs.worldbank.org/youth-transforming-africa/senegals-youth-oers-
inspiring-creativity-ght-covid-19, accessed 9 July 2020).
86. Abi-Rached JM, Issa N, Khalife J, Salameh P, Karra-Aly A, Asmar MK. Towards a zero-COVID Lebanon: A call for action. Paris:
Arab Reform Initiative; 2020 (https://www.arab-reform.net/publication/towards-a-zero-covid-lebanon-a-call-for-action/,
accessed 5 October 2020).
87. Transparency data. List of participants of SAGE and related sub-groups. London HM Government; 2020 (https://www.
gov.uk/government/publications/scientic-advisory-group-for-emergencies-sage-coronavirus-covid-19-response-
membership/list-of-participants-of-sage-and-related-sub-groups, accessed 16 November 2020).
88. Independent SAGE (https://www.independentsage.org/, accessed 3 November 2020).
89. Connecting to Congress (on the COVID-19 emergency). Vancouver: Participedia; 2020 (https://participedia.net/case/6560,
accessed 4 November 2020).
90. Endcoronavirus.org (https://www.endcoronavirus.org, accessed 2 November 2020).
91. Erkhembayar R, Dickinson E, Badarch D, Narula I, Warburton D, Thomas GN, et al. Early policy actions and emergency
response to the COVID-19 pandemic in Mongolia: experiences and challenges. Lancet Glob Health. 2020;8(9):e1234–41.
92. Mongolia: Civic engagement in decision making (MN0024). Washington DC: Open Government Partnership; 2020 (www.
opengovpartnership.org/members/mongolia/commitments/MN0024/, accessed 5 November 2020).
23
References
93. Jeeries S, French N, Gilkison C, Graham G, Hope V, Marshall J, et al. COVID-19 in New Zealand and the impact of the
national response: a descriptive epidemiological study. Lancet Public Health. 2020;5(11):e612–23.
94. Community engagement. Wellington: New Zealand Department of the Prime Minister and Cabinet; 2020 (https://dpmc.
govt.nz/our-programmes/policy-project/policy-methods-toolbox/community-engagement, accessed 5 November 2020).
95. Lessons from Rwanda for COVID-19. Palo Alto (CA): Emmerson Collective; 2020 (https://www.emersoncollective.com/
articles/2020/04/lessons-from-rwanda-for-covid-19/, accessed 5 November 2020).
96. Commission d’enquête pour l’évaluation des politiques publiques face aux grandes pandémies à la lumière de la crise
sanitaire de la COVID-19 et de sa gestion [Enquiry committee for the evaluation of public policy on large pandemics in
the light of the health crisis of COVID-19 and its management]. Paris: Senate; 2020 (http://www.senat.fr/commission/
enquete/gestion_de_la_crise_sanitaire.html, accessed 14 November 2020).
97. Dimitrova A. Grenoble turns to citizens for the handling of the health crisis. Bratislava: TheMayor.eu; 2020 (https://www.
themayor.eu/sk/grenoble-turns-to-citizens-for-the-handling-of-the-health-crisis, accessed 14 November 2020).